Contents 1 Biography 1.1 Early life 1.1.1 Birth and family 1.1.2 Name 1.1.3 Education 1.2 Later life 1.3 Death 2 Intellectual influences on Plato 2.1 Pythagoras 2.2 Heraclitus and Parmenides 2.3 Socrates 3 Plato's use of myth 4 Philosophy 4.1 Recurrent themes 4.2 Metaphysics 4.3 Theory of Forms 4.4 Epistemology 4.5 The state 4.6 Unwritten doctrines 4.7 Dialectic 5 Dialogues 5.1 Writings of doubted authenticity 5.1.1 Spurious writings 5.2 Composition of the dialogues 5.3 Narration of the dialogues 5.4 Trial of Socrates 5.5 Unity and diversity of the dialogues 5.6 Platonic scholarship 5.7 Textual sources and history 5.8 Modern editions 6 Plato in arts 7 See also 8 Notes 9 Citations 10 References 10.1 Primary sources (Greek and Roman) 10.2 Secondary sources 11 Further reading 12 External links


Biography Early life Main article: Early life of Plato Due to a lack of surviving accounts, little is known about Plato's early life and education. The philosopher came from one of the wealthiest and most politically active families in Athens. Ancient sources describe him as a bright though modest boy who excelled in his studies. His father contributed all which was necessary to give to his son a good education, and, therefore, Plato must have been instructed in grammar, music, gymnastics and philosophy by some of the most distinguished teachers of his era. Birth and family The exact time and place of Plato's birth are unknown, but it is certain that he belonged to an aristocratic and influential family. Based on ancient sources, most modern scholars believe that he was born in Athens or Aegina[c] between 429 and 423 BC. His father was Ariston. According to a disputed tradition, reported by Diogenes Laertius, Ariston traced his descent from the king of Athens, Codrus, and the king of Messenia, Melanthus.[11] Plato's mother was Perictione, whose family boasted of a relationship with the famous Athenian lawmaker and lyric poet Solon.[12] Perictione was sister of Charmides and niece of Critias, both prominent figures of the Thirty Tyrants, the brief oligarchic regime, which followed on the collapse of Athens at the end of the Peloponnesian War (404–403 BC).[13] Besides Plato himself, Ariston and Perictione had three other children; these were two sons, Adeimantus and Glaucon, and a daughter Potone, the mother of Speusippus (the nephew and successor of Plato as head of his philosophical Academy).[13] The brothers Adeimantus and Glaucon are mentioned in the Republic as sons of Ariston,[14] and presumably brothers of Plato, but some have argued they were uncles.[15] But in a scenario in the Memorabilia, Xenophon confused the issue by presenting a Glaucon much younger than Plato.[16] The traditional date of Plato's birth (428/427) is based on a dubious interpretation of Diogenes Laertius, who says, "When [Socrates] was gone, [Plato] joined Cratylus the Heracleitean and Hermogenes, who philosophized in the manner of Parmenides. Then, at twenty-eight, Hermodorus says, [Plato] went to Euclides in Megara." As Debra Nails argues, "The text itself gives no reason to infer that Plato left immediately for Megara and implies the very opposite."[17] In his Seventh Letter, Plato notes that his coming of age coincided with the taking of power by the Thirty, remarking, "But a youth under the age of twenty made himself a laughingstock if he attempted to enter the political arena." Thus, Nails dates Plato's birth to 424/423.[18] According to some accounts, Ariston tried to force his attentions on Perictione, but failed in his purpose; then the god Apollo appeared to him in a vision, and as a result, Ariston left Perictione unmolested.[19] Another legend related that, when Plato was an infant, bees settled on his lips while he was sleeping: an augury of the sweetness of style in which he would discourse about philosophy.[20] Ariston appears to have died in Plato's childhood, although the precise dating of his death is difficult.[21] Perictione then married Pyrilampes, her mother's brother,[22] who had served many times as an ambassador to the Persian court and was a friend of Pericles, the leader of the democratic faction in Athens.[23] Pyrilampes had a son from a previous marriage, Demus, who was famous for his beauty.[24] Perictione gave birth to Pyrilampes' second son, Antiphon, the half-brother of Plato, who appears in Parmenides.[25] In contrast to reticence about himself, Plato often introduced his distinguished relatives into his dialogues, or referred to them with some precision: Charmides has a dialogue named after him; Critias speaks in both Charmides and Protagoras; and Adeimantus and Glaucon take prominent parts in the Republic.[26] These and other references suggest a considerable amount of family pride and enable us to reconstruct Plato's family tree. According to Burnet, "the opening scene of the Charmides is a glorification of the whole [family] connection ... Plato's dialogues are not only a memorial to Socrates, but also the happier days of his own family."[27] Name According to Diogenes Laërtius, the philosopher was named Aristocles (Ἀριστοκλῆς) after his grandfather.[28] It was common in Athenian society for boys to be named after grandfathers (or fathers). But there is only one inscriptional record of an Aristocles, an early Archon of Athens in 605/4 BC. There is no record of a line from Aristocles to Plato's father, Ariston. However, if Plato was not named after an ancestor named Plato (there is no record of one), then the origin of his renaming as Plato becomes a conundrum.[29] The sources of Diogenes account for this fact by claiming that his wrestling coach, Ariston of Argos, dubbed him Platon, meaning "broad," on account of his robust figure[30] or that Plato derived his name from the breadth (πλατύτης, platytēs) of his eloquence, or else because he was very wide (πλατύς, platýs) across the forehead.[31] Recently a scholar has argued that even the name Aristocles for Plato was a much later invention.[32] Although Platon was a fairly common name (31 instances are known from Athens alone[33]), the name does not occur in Plato's known family line. Another scholar, however, claims that "there is good reason for not dismissing [the idea that Aristocles was Plato's given name] as a mere invention of his biographers", noting how prevalent that account is in our sources.[29] The fact that the philosopher in his maturity called himself Platon is indisputable, but the origin of this naming must remain moot unless the record is made to yield more information. Education Bust excavated at the Villa of the Papyri, attributed to Dionysus, Plato or Poseidon. The bust may represent an idealized imagining of what Plato might have looked like at middle age. Apuleius informs us that Speusippus praised Plato's quickness of mind and modesty as a boy, and the "first fruits of his youth infused with hard work and love of study".[34] Plato must have been instructed in grammar, music, and gymnastics by the most distinguished teachers of his time.[35] Dicaearchus went so far as to say that Plato wrestled at the Isthmian games.[36] Plato had also attended courses of philosophy; before meeting Socrates, he first became acquainted with Cratylus (a disciple of Heraclitus, a prominent pre-Socratic Greek philosopher) and the Heraclitean doctrines.[37] Ambrose believed that Plato met Jeremiah in Egypt and was influenced by his ideas. Augustine initially accepted this claim, but later rejected it, arguing in "The City of God", that "Plato was born a hundred years after Jeremiah prophesied." [38] Hebrew-language chronology works[by whom?] argue that, based on seder hadoroth chronology, Jeremiah's final year of prophecy was 411 BCE (3350 HC), at which time Plato was a teenager[39] and that he initially perceived Jeremiah to be absurd.[40][need quotation to verify] Later life Plato may have traveled in Italy, Sicily, Egypt and Cyrene.[41] Said to have returned to Athens at the age of forty, Plato founded one of the earliest known organized schools in Western Civilization on a plot of land in the Grove of Hecademus or Academus.[42] The Academy was a large enclosure of ground about six stadia outside of Athens proper. One story is that the name of the Academy comes from the ancient hero, Academus; still another story is that the name came from a supposed former owner of the plot of land, an Athenian citizen whose name was (also) Academus; while yet another account is that it was named after a member of the army of Castor and Pollux, an Arcadian named Echedemus.[43] The Academy operated until it was destroyed by Lucius Cornelius Sulla in 84 BC. Neoplatonists revived the Academy in the early 5th century, and it operated until 529 AD, when it was closed by Justinian I of Byzantium, who saw it as a threat to the propagation of Christianity. Many intellectuals were schooled in the Academy, the most prominent one being Aristotle.[44][45] Throughout his later life, Plato became entangled with the politics of the city of Syracuse. According to Diogenes Laertius, Plato initially visited Syracuse while it was under the rule of Dionysius.[46] During this first trip Dionysius's brother-in-law, Dion of Syracuse, became one of Plato's disciples, but the tyrant himself turned against Plato. Plato almost faced death, but he was sold into slavery. Then Anniceris[47] bought Plato's freedom for twenty minas,[48] and sent him home. After Dionysius's death, according to Plato's Seventh Letter, Dion requested Plato return to Syracuse to tutor Dionysius II and guide him to become a philosopher king. Dionysius II seemed to accept Plato's teachings, but he became suspicious of Dion, his uncle. Dionysius expelled Dion and kept Plato against his will. Eventually Plato left Syracuse. Dion would return to overthrow Dionysius and ruled Syracuse for a short time before being usurped by Calippus, a fellow disciple of Plato. Death A variety of sources have given accounts of Plato's death. One story, based on a mutilated manuscript,[49] suggests Plato died in his bed, whilst a young Thracian girl played the flute to him.[50] Another tradition suggests Plato died at a wedding feast. The account is based on Diogenes Laertius's reference to an account by Hermippus, a third-century Alexandrian.[51] According to Tertullian, Plato simply died in his sleep.[51]


Intellectual influences on Plato Pythagoras Bust of Pythagoras based on traditional iconography at the Museum Capitolini, Rome. See also: Pythagoreanism Although Socrates influenced Plato directly as related in the dialogues, the influence of Pythagoras upon Plato also appears to have significant discussion in the philosophical literature. Pythagoras, or in a broader sense, the Pythagoreans, allegedly exercised an important influence on the work of Plato. According to R. M. Hare, this influence consists of three points: (1) The platonic Republic might be related to the idea of "a tightly organized community of like-minded thinkers", like the one established by Pythagoras in Croton. (2) There is evidence that Plato possibly took from Pythagoras the idea that mathematics and, generally speaking, abstract thinking is a secure basis for philosophical thinking as well as "for substantial theses in science and morals". (3) Plato and Pythagoras shared a "mystical approach to the soul and its place in the material world". It is probable that both were influenced by Orphism.[52][53] Pythagoras held that all things are number, and the cosmos comes from numerical principles. The physical world of becoming is an imitation of the mathematical world of being. This ideas were very influential in Heraclitus, Parmenides and Plato.[54] Aristotle claimed that the philosophy of Plato closely followed the teachings of the Pythagoreans,[55] and Cicero repeats this claim: "They say Plato learned all things Pythagorean" (Platonem ferunt didicisse Pythagorea omnia).[56] George Karamanolis notes that "Numenius accepted both Pythagoras and Plato as the two authorities one should follow in philosophy, but he regarded Plato's authority as subordinate to that of Pythagoras, whom he considered to be the source of all true philosophy—including Plato's own. For Numenius it is just that Plato wrote so many philosophical works, whereas Pythagoras' views were originally passed on only orally."[57] Heraclitus and Parmenides Heraclitus (1628) by Hendrick ter Brugghen Bust of Parmenides from Velia See also: Metaphysics These two philosophers, following the way initiated by the pre-Socratic Greek philosophers, particularly Pythagoras, depart from the mythological tradition, and initiate the metaphysical philosophical approach, that strongly influenced Plato and has arrived till our days.[54] Heraclitus thinking specially remarked the fact that all things are continuously changing, or becoming. It is well known his image of the river, with ever-changing waters. Plato received the ideas of this philosopher through Cratylus, that emphasized even more than his teacher the idea of change; and considered that this vision of continuous change leads to skepticism, since we can not define a thing that has not a permanent nature.[58] Parmenides adopted an altogether contrary vision, and emphasized the idea of changeless Being, and considered that change is an illusion of the senses.[54] John Palmer notes "Parmenides’ distinction among the principal modes of being and his derivation of the attributes that must belong to what must be, simply as such, qualify him to be seen as the founder of metaphysics or ontology as a domain of inquiry distinct from theology."[59] These ideas about change and permanence, or becoming and Being, was the influence that led Plato to formulate his theory of forms. According to it, there is a world of perfect, eternal and changeless forms, the realm of Being, and an imperfect sensible world of becoming that partakes the qualities of the forms, and is its instantiation in the sensible world.[58] Socrates Main article: Socratic problem Socrates bust Louvre. The precise relationship between Plato and Socrates remains an area of contention among scholars. Plato makes it clear in his Apology of Socrates that he was a devoted young follower of Socrates. In that dialogue, Socrates is presented as mentioning Plato by name as one of those youths close enough to him to have been corrupted, if he were in fact guilty of corrupting the youth, and questioning why their fathers and brothers did not step forward to testify against him if he was indeed guilty of such a crime (33d-34a). Later, Plato is mentioned along with Crito, Critobolus, and Apollodorus as offering to pay a fine of 30 minas on Socrates' behalf, in lieu of the death penalty proposed by Meletus (38b). In the Phaedo, the title character lists those who were in attendance at the prison on Socrates' last day, explaining Plato's absence by saying, "Plato was ill." (Phaedo 59b) Plato never speaks in his own voice in his dialogues. In the Second Letter, it says, "no writing of Plato exists or ever will exist, but those now said to be his are those of a Socrates become beautiful and new" (341c); if the Letter is Plato's, the final qualification seems to call into question the dialogues' historical fidelity. In any case, Xenophon and Aristophanes seem to present a somewhat different portrait of Socrates from the one Plato paints. Some have called attention to the problem of taking Plato's Socrates to be his mouthpiece, given Socrates' reputation for irony and the dramatic nature of the dialogue form.[60] Aristotle attributes a different doctrine with respect to Forms to Plato and Socrates (Metaphysics 987b1–11). Aristotle suggests that Socrates' idea of forms can be discovered through investigation of the natural world, unlike Plato's Forms that exist beyond and outside the ordinary range of human understanding.


Plato's use of myth Mythos and logos are terms that evolved along classical Greece history. In the times of Homer and Hesiod (eighth century BC) they were quite synonyms, and contained the meaning of tale or history. Later came historians like Herodotus and Thucydides, as well as philosophers as Parmenides and other Presocratics that introduced a distinction between both terms, and mythos became more a non verifiable account, and logos a rational account.[61] Plato, being a disciple of Socrates, and a strong partisan of philosophy based on logos, it seems that should have avoided the use of myth telling. Instead he made an abundant use of it. This fact has produced analytical and interpretative work, in order to clarify the reasons and purposes for that use. Plato, in general, distinguished between three types of myth. First there were the false myths, like those based on stories of gods subject to passions and sufferings, because reason teaches that God is perfect. Then came the myths based on true reasoning, and therefore also true. Finally there were those non verifiable because beyond of human reason, but containing some truth in them. Regarding the subjects of Plato's myths they are of two types, those dealing with the origin of the universe, and those about morals and the origin and fate of the soul.[62] It is generally agreed that the main purpose for Plato in using myths was didactic. He considered that only a few people were capable or interested in following a reasoned philosophical discourse, but men in general are attracted by stories and tales. Consequently then, he used the myth to convey the conclusions of the philosophical reasoning. Some of Plato's myths were based in traditional ones, others were modifications of them, and finally he also invented altogether new myths.[63] For the use of the term allegory see note [d]


Philosophy As old man, Plato (left) and Aristotle (right), a detail of The School of Athens, a fresco by Raphael. Aristotle gestures to the earth, representing his belief in knowledge through empirical observation and experience, while holding a copy of his Nicomachean Ethics in his hand. Plato holds his Timaeus and gestures to the heavens, representing his belief in The Forms. Recurrent themes Plato often discusses the father-son relationship and the question of whether a father's interest in his sons has much to do with how well his sons turn out. In ancient Athens, a boy was socially located by his family identity, and Plato often refers to his characters in terms of their paternal and fraternal relationships. Socrates was not a family man, and saw himself as the son of his mother, who was apparently a midwife. A divine fatalist, Socrates mocks men who spent exorbitant fees on tutors and trainers for their sons, and repeatedly ventures the idea that good character is a gift from the gods. Plato's dialogue Crito reminds Socrates that orphans are at the mercy of chance, but Socrates is unconcerned. In the Theaetetus, he is found recruiting as a disciple a young man whose inheritance has been squandered. Socrates twice compares the relationship of the older man and his boy lover to the father-son relationship (Lysis 213a, Republic 3.403b), and in the Phaedo, Socrates' disciples, towards whom he displays more concern than his biological sons, say they will feel "fatherless" when he is gone. In several of Plato's dialogues, Socrates promulgates the idea that knowledge is a matter of recollection, and not of learning, observation, or study.[64] He maintains this view somewhat at his own expense, because in many dialogues, Socrates complains of his forgetfulness. Socrates is often found arguing that knowledge is not empirical, and that it comes from divine insight. In many middle period dialogues, such as the Phaedo, Republic and Phaedrus Plato advocates a belief in the immortality of the soul, and several dialogues end with long speeches imagining the afterlife. More than one dialogue contrasts knowledge and opinion, perception and reality, nature and custom, and body and soul. Several dialogues tackle questions about art: Socrates says that poetry is inspired by the muses, and is not rational. He speaks approvingly of this, and other forms of divine madness (drunkenness, eroticism, and dreaming) in the Phaedrus (265a–c), and yet in the Republic wants to outlaw Homer's great poetry, and laughter as well. In Ion, Socrates gives no hint of the disapproval of Homer that he expresses in the Republic. The dialogue Ion suggests that Homer's Iliad functioned in the ancient Greek world as the Bible does today in the modern Christian world: as divinely inspired literature that can provide moral guidance, if only it can be properly interpreted. Socrates and his company of disputants had something to say on many subjects, including politics and art, religion and science, justice and medicine, virtue and vice, crime and punishment, pleasure and pain, rhetoric and rhapsody, human nature and sexuality, as well as love and wisdom. Metaphysics Main article: Platonic realism "Platonism" is a term coined by scholars to refer to the intellectual consequences of denying, as Plato's Socrates often does, the reality of the material world. In several dialogues, most notably the Republic, Socrates inverts the common man's intuition about what is knowable and what is real. While most people take the objects of their senses to be real if anything is, Socrates is contemptuous of people who think that something has to be graspable in the hands to be real. In the Theaetetus, he says such people are eu amousoi (εὖ ἄμουσοι), an expression that means literally, "happily without the muses" (Theaetetus 156a). In other words, such people live without the divine inspiration that gives him, and people like him, access to higher insights about reality. Socrates' idea that reality is unavailable to those who use their senses is what puts him at odds with the common man, and with common sense. Socrates says that he who sees with his eyes is blind, and this idea is most famously captured in his Allegory of the Cave, and more explicitly in his description of the divided line. The Allegory of the Cave (begins Republic 7.514a) is a paradoxical analogy wherein Socrates argues that the invisible world is the most intelligible ("noeton") and that the visible world ("(h)oraton") is the least knowable, and the most obscure. Socrates says in the Republic that people who take the sun-lit world of the senses to be good and real are living pitifully in a den of evil and ignorance. Socrates admits that few climb out of the den, or cave of ignorance, and those who do, not only have a terrible struggle to attain the heights, but when they go back down for a visit or to help other people up, they find themselves objects of scorn and ridicule. According to Socrates, physical objects and physical events are "shadows" of their ideal or perfect forms, and exist only to the extent that they instantiate the perfect versions of themselves. Just as shadows are temporary, inconsequential epiphenomena produced by physical objects, physical objects are themselves fleeting phenomena caused by more substantial causes, the ideals of which they are mere instances. For example, Socrates thinks that perfect justice exists (although it is not clear where) and his own trial would be a cheap copy of it. The Allegory of the Cave (often said by scholars to represent Plato's own epistemology and metaphysics) is intimately connected to his political ideology (often said to also be Plato's own), that only people who have climbed out of the cave and cast their eyes on a vision of goodness are fit to rule. Socrates claims that the enlightened men of society must be forced from their divine contemplations and be compelled to run the city according to their lofty insights. Thus is born the idea of the "philosopher-king", the wise person who accepts the power thrust upon him by the people who are wise enough to choose a good master. This is the main thesis of Socrates in the Republic, that the most wisdom the masses can muster is the wise choice of a ruler.[65] Theory of Forms Main article: Theory of Forms The theory of Forms (or theory of Ideas) typically refers to the belief that the material world as it seems to us is not the real world, but only an "image" or "copy" of the real world. In some of Plato's dialogues, this is expressed by Socrates, who spoke of forms in formulating a solution to the problem of universals. The forms, according to Socrates, are archetypes or abstract representations of the many types of things, and properties we feel and see around us, that can only be perceived by reason (Greek: λογική). (That is, they are universals.) In other words, Socrates was able to recognize two worlds: the apparent world, which constantly changes, and an unchanging and unseen world of forms, which may be the cause of what is apparent. Epistemology Main article: Platonic epistemology Many have interpreted Plato as stating—even having been the first to write—that knowledge is justified true belief, an influential view that informed future developments in epistemology.[66] This interpretation is partly based on a reading of the Theaetetus wherein Plato argues that knowledge is distinguished from mere true belief by the knower having an "account" of the object of her or his true belief (Theaetetus 201c–d). And this theory may again be seen in the Meno, where it is suggested that true belief can be raised to the level of knowledge if it is bound with an account as to the question of "why" the object of the true belief is so (Meno 97d–98a).[67] Many years later, Edmund Gettier famously demonstrated the problems of the justified true belief account of knowledge. That the modern theory of justified true belief as knowledge which Gettier addresses is equivalent to Plato's is accepted by some scholars but rejected by others.[68] Plato himself also identified problems with the justified true belief definition in the Theaetetus, concluding that justification (or an "account") would require knowledge of differentness, meaning that the definition of knowledge is circular (Theaetetus 210a–b).[69] Later in the Meno, Socrates uses a geometrical example to expound Plato's view that knowledge in this latter sense is acquired by recollection. Socrates elicits a fact concerning a geometrical construction from a slave boy, who could not have otherwise known the fact (due to the slave boy's lack of education). The knowledge must be present, Socrates concludes, in an eternal, non-experiential form. In other dialogues, the Sophist, Statesman, Republic, and the Parmenides, Plato himself associates knowledge with the apprehension of unchanging Forms and their relationships to one another (which he calls "expertise" in Dialectic), including through the processes of collection and division.[70] More explicitly, Plato himself argues in the Timaeus that knowledge is always proportionate to the realm from which it is gained. In other words, if one derives one's account of something experientially, because the world of sense is in flux, the views therein attained will be mere opinions. And opinions are characterized by a lack of necessity and stability. On the other hand, if one derives one's account of something by way of the non-sensible forms, because these forms are unchanging, so too is the account derived from them. That apprehension of forms is required for knowledge may be taken to cohere with Plato's theory in the Theaetetus and Meno.[71] Indeed, the apprehension of Forms may be at the base of the "account" required for justification, in that it offers foundational knowledge which itself needs no account, thereby avoiding an infinite regression.[72] The state Main article: The Republic (Plato) Oxyrhynchus Papyri, with fragment of Plato's Republic Plato's philosophical views had many societal implications, especially on the idea of an ideal state or government. There is some discrepancy between his early and later views. Some of the most famous doctrines are contained in the Republic during his middle period, as well as in the Laws and the Statesman. However, because Plato wrote dialogues, it is assumed that Socrates is often speaking for Plato. This assumption may not be true in all cases. Plato, through the words of Socrates, asserts that societies have a tripartite class structure corresponding to the appetite/spirit/reason structure of the individual soul. The appetite/spirit/reason are analogous to the castes of society.[73] Productive (Workers) – the labourers, carpenters, plumbers, masons, merchants, farmers, ranchers, etc. These correspond to the "appetite" part of the soul. Protective (Warriors or Guardians) – those who are adventurous, strong and brave; in the armed forces. These correspond to the "spirit" part of the soul. Governing (Rulers or Philosopher Kings) – those who are intelligent, rational, self-controlled, in love with wisdom, well suited to make decisions for the community. These correspond to the "reason" part of the soul and are very few. In the Timaeus, Plato locates the parts of the soul within the human body: Reason is located in the head, spirit in the top third of the torso, and the appetite in the middle third of the torso, down to the navel.[74][75] According to this model, the principles of Athenian democracy (as it existed in his day) are rejected as only a few are fit to rule. Instead of rhetoric and persuasion, Plato says reason and wisdom should govern. As Plato puts it: "Until philosophers rule as kings or those who are now called kings and leading men genuinely and adequately philosophise, that is, until political power and philosophy entirely coincide, while the many natures who at present pursue either one exclusively are forcibly prevented from doing so, cities will have no rest from evils,... nor, I think, will the human race." (Republic 473c–d) Plato in his academy, drawing after a painting by Swedish painter Carl Johan Wahlbom Plato describes these "philosopher kings" as "those who love the sight of truth" (Republic 475c) and supports the idea with the analogy of a captain and his ship or a doctor and his medicine. According to him, sailing and health are not things that everyone is qualified to practice by nature. A large part of the Republic then addresses how the educational system should be set up to produce these philosopher kings. However, it must be taken into account that the ideal city outlined in the Republic is qualified by Socrates as the ideal luxurious city, examined to determine how it is that injustice and justice grow in a city (Republic 372e). According to Socrates, the "true" and "healthy" city is instead the one first outlined in book II of the Republic, 369c–372d, containing farmers, craftsmen, merchants, and wage-earners, but lacking the guardian class of philosopher-kings as well as delicacies such as "perfumed oils, incense, prostitutes, and pastries", in addition to paintings, gold, ivory, couches, a multitude of occupations such as poets and hunters, and war. In addition, the ideal city is used as an image to illuminate the state of one's soul, or the will, reason, and desires combined in the human body. Socrates is attempting to make an image of a rightly ordered human, and then later goes on to describe the different kinds of humans that can be observed, from tyrants to lovers of money in various kinds of cities. The ideal city is not promoted, but only used to magnify the different kinds of individual humans and the state of their soul. However, the philosopher king image was used by many after Plato to justify their personal political beliefs. The philosophic soul according to Socrates has reason, will, and desires united in virtuous harmony. A philosopher has the moderate love for wisdom and the courage to act according to wisdom. Wisdom is knowledge about the Good or the right relations between all that exists. Wherein it concerns states and rulers, Plato has made interesting arguments. For instance he asks which is better—a bad democracy or a country reigned by a tyrant. He argues that it is better to be ruled by a bad tyrant, than by a bad democracy (since here all the people are now responsible for such actions, rather than one individual committing many bad deeds.) This is emphasised within the Republic as Plato describes the event of mutiny on board a ship.[76] Plato suggests the ship's crew to be in line with the democratic rule of many and the captain, although inhibited through ailments, the tyrant. Plato's description of this event is parallel to that of democracy within the state and the inherent problems that arise. According to Plato, a state made up of different kinds of souls will, overall, decline from an aristocracy (rule by the best) to a timocracy (rule by the honorable), then to an oligarchy (rule by the few), then to a democracy (rule by the people), and finally to tyranny (rule by one person, rule by a tyrant).[77] Aristocracy is the form of government (politeia) advocated in Plato's Republic. This regime is ruled by a philosopher king, and thus is grounded on wisdom and reason. The aristocratic state, and the man whose nature corresponds to it, are the objects of Plato's analyses throughout much of the Republic, as opposed to the other four types of states/men, who are discussed later in his work. In Book VIII, Plato states in order the other four imperfect societies with a description of the state's structure and individual character. In timocracy the ruling class is made up primarily of those with a warrior-like character.[78] In his description, Plato has Sparta in mind. Oligarchy is made up of a society in which wealth is the criterion of merit and the wealthy are in control.[79] In democracy, the state bears resemblance to ancient Athens with traits such as equality of political opportunity and freedom for the individual to do as he likes.[80] Democracy then degenerates into tyranny from the conflict of rich and poor. It is characterized by an undisciplined society existing in chaos, where the tyrant rises as popular champion leading to the formation of his private army and the growth of oppression.[81][77][82] Unwritten doctrines Main article: Plato's unwritten doctrines For a long time, Plato's unwritten doctrine[83][84][85] had been controversial. Many modern books on Plato seem to diminish its importance; nevertheless, the first important witness who mentions its existence is Aristotle, who in his Physics (209 b) writes: "It is true, indeed, that the account he gives there [i.e. in Timaeus] of the participant is different from what he says in his so-called unwritten teachings (ἄγραφα δόγματα)." The term "ἄγραφα δόγματα" literally means unwritten doctrines and it stands for the most fundamental metaphysical teaching of Plato, which he disclosed only orally, and some say only to his most trusted fellows, and which he may have kept secret from the public. The importance of the unwritten doctrines does not seem to have been seriously questioned before the 19th century. A reason for not revealing it to everyone is partially discussed in Phaedrus (276 c) where Plato criticizes the written transmission of knowledge as faulty, favoring instead the spoken logos: "he who has knowledge of the just and the good and beautiful ... will not, when in earnest, write them in ink, sowing them through a pen with words, which cannot defend themselves by argument and cannot teach the truth effectually." The same argument is repeated in Plato's Seventh Letter (344 c): "every serious man in dealing with really serious subjects carefully avoids writing." In the same letter he writes (341 c): "I can certainly declare concerning all these writers who claim to know the subjects that I seriously study ... there does not exist, nor will there ever exist, any treatise of mine dealing therewith." Such secrecy is necessary in order not "to expose them to unseemly and degrading treatment" (344 d). It is, however, said that Plato once disclosed this knowledge to the public in his lecture On the Good (Περὶ τἀγαθοῦ), in which the Good (τὸ ἀγαθόν) is identified with the One (the Unity, τὸ ἕν), the fundamental ontological principle. The content of this lecture has been transmitted by several witnesses. Aristoxenus describes the event in the following words: "Each came expecting to learn something about the things that are generally considered good for men, such as wealth, good health, physical strength, and altogether a kind of wonderful happiness. But when the mathematical demonstrations came, including numbers, geometrical figures and astronomy, and finally the statement Good is One seemed to them, I imagine, utterly unexpected and strange; hence some belittled the matter, while others rejected it."[86] Simplicius quotes Alexander of Aphrodisias, who states that "according to Plato, the first principles of everything, including the Forms themselves are One and Indefinite Duality (ἡ ἀόριστος δυάς), which he called Large and Small (τὸ μέγα καὶ τὸ μικρόν)", and Simplicius reports as well that "one might also learn this from Speusippus and Xenocrates and the others who were present at Plato's lecture on the Good".[32] Their account is in full agreement with Aristotle's description of Plato's metaphysical doctrine. In Metaphysics he writes: "Now since the Forms are the causes of everything else, he [i.e. Plato] supposed that their elements are the elements of all things. Accordingly the material principle is the Great and Small [i.e. the Dyad], and the essence is the One (τὸ ἕν), since the numbers are derived from the Great and Small by participation in the One" (987 b). "From this account it is clear that he only employed two causes: that of the essence, and the material cause; for the Forms are the cause of the essence in everything else, and the One is the cause of it in the Forms. He also tells us what the material substrate is of which the Forms are predicated in the case of sensible things, and the One in that of the Forms - that it is this the duality (the Dyad, ἡ δυάς), the Great and Small (τὸ μέγα καὶ τὸ μικρόν). Further, he assigned to these two elements respectively the causation of good and of evil" (988 a). The most important aspect of this interpretation of Plato's metaphysics is the continuity between his teaching and the neoplatonic interpretation of Plotinus[87] or Ficino[88] which has been considered erroneous by many but may in fact have been directly influenced by oral transmission of Plato's doctrine. A modern scholar who recognized the importance of the unwritten doctrine of Plato was Heinrich Gomperz who described it in his speech during the 7th International Congress of Philosophy in 1930.[89] All the sources related to the ἄγραφα δόγματα have been collected by Konrad Gaiser and published as Testimonia Platonica.[90] These sources have subsequently been interpreted by scholars from the German Tübingen School of interpretation such as Hans Joachim Krämer or Thomas A. Szlezák.[91] Dialectic The role of dialectic in Plato's thought is contested but there are two main interpretations: a type of reasoning and a method of intuition.[92] Simon Blackburn adopts the first, saying that Plato's dialectic is "the process of eliciting the truth by means of questions aimed at opening out what is already implicitly known, or at exposing the contradictions and muddles of an opponent's position."[92] A similar interpretation has been put forth by Louis Hartz, who suggests that elements of the dialectic are borrowed from Hegel.[93] According to this view, opposing arguments improve upon each other, and prevailing opinion is shaped by the synthesis of many conflicting ideas over time. Each new idea exposes a flaw in the accepted model, and the epistemological substance of the debate continually approaches the truth. Hartz's is a teleological interpretation at the core, in which philosophers will ultimately exhaust the available body of knowledge and thus reach "the end of history." Karl Popper, on the other hand, claims that dialectic is the art of intuition for "visualising the divine originals, the Forms or Ideas, of unveiling the Great Mystery behind the common man's everyday world of appearances."[94]


Dialogues See also: Stephanus pagination Thirty-five dialogues and thirteen letters (the Epistles) have traditionally been ascribed to Plato, though modern scholarship doubts the authenticity of at least some of these. Plato's writings have been published in several fashions; this has led to several conventions regarding the naming and referencing of Plato's texts. The usual system for making unique references to sections of the text by Plato derives from a 16th-century edition of Plato's works by Henricus Stephanus. An overview of Plato's writings according to this system can be found in the Stephanus pagination article. Volume 3, pages 32–33, of the 1578 Stephanus edition of Plato, showing a passage of Timaeus with the Latin translation and notes of Jean de Serres One tradition regarding the arrangement of Plato's texts is according to tetralogies. This scheme is ascribed by Diogenes Laertius to an ancient scholar and court astrologer to Tiberius named Thrasyllus. The works are usually grouped into Early (sometimes by some into Transitional), Middle, and Late period.[95][96] This choice to group chronologically is thought worthy of criticism by some (Cooper et al),[97] given that it's recognised that there is no absolute agreement as to the true chronologicity, since the facts of the temporal order of writing are not confidently ascertained.[98] Early: Apology (of Socrates), Charmides, Crito, Euthyphro, Gorgias, (Lesser) Hippias (minor), (Greater) Hippias (major), Ion, Laches, Lysis, Protagoras Middle/Transitional: Cratylus, Euthydemus, Meno, Parmenides, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Republic, Symposium, Middle/Late: Theaetetus Late: Critias, Sophist, Statesman / Politicus, Timaeus, Philebus, Laws Chronologicity was not a consideration in ancient times, in that grouping of this nature are virtually absent (Tarrant) in the extant writings of ancient Platonists.[99] Writings of doubted authenticity Jowett mentions in his Appendix to Menexenus, that works which bore the character of a writer were attributed to that writer even when the actual author was unknown.[100] For below: (*) if there is no consensus among scholars as to whether Plato is the author, and (‡) if most scholars agree that Plato is not the author of the work.[101] First Alcibiades (*), Second Alcibiades (‡), Clitophon (*), Epinomis (‡), Epistles (*), Hipparchus (‡), Menexenus (*), Minos (‡), (Rival) Lovers (‡), Theages (‡) Spurious writings The following works were transmitted under Plato's name, most of them already considered spurious in antiquity, and so were not included by Thrasyllus in his tetralogical arrangement. These works are labelled as Notheuomenoi ("spurious") or Apocrypha. Axiochus, Definitions, Demodocus, Epigrams, Eryxias, Halcyon, On Justice, On Virtue, Sisyphus. Composition of the dialogues No one knows the exact order Plato's dialogues were written in, nor the extent to which some might have been later revised and rewritten. A significant distinction of the early Plato and the later Plato has been offered by scholars such as E.R. Dodds and has been summarized by Harold Bloom in his book titled Agon: "E.R. Dodds is the classical scholar whose writings most illuminated the Hellenic descent (in) The Greeks and the Irrational [...] In his chapter on Plato and the Irrational Soul [...] Dodds traces Plato's spiritual evolution from the pure rationalist of the Protagoras to the transcendental psychologist, influenced by the Pythagoreans and Orphics, of the later works culminating in the Laws."[102] Lewis Campbell was the first[103] to make exhaustive use of stylometry to prove objectively that the Critias, Timaeus, Laws, Philebus, Sophist, and Statesman were all clustered together as a group, while the Parmenides, Phaedrus, Republic, and Theaetetus belong to a separate group, which must be earlier (given Aristotle's statement in his Politics[104] that the Laws was written after the Republic; cf. Diogenes Laertius Lives 3.37). What is remarkable about Campbell's conclusions is that, in spite of all the stylometric studies that have been conducted since his time, perhaps the only chronological fact about Plato's works that can now be said to be proven by stylometry is the fact that Critias, Timaeus, Laws, Philebus, Sophist, and Statesman are the latest of Plato's dialogues, the others earlier.[105] Increasingly in the most recent Plato scholarship, writers are skeptical of the notion that the order of Plato's writings can be established with any precision,[106] though Plato's works are still often characterized as falling at least roughly into three groups.[107] The following represents one relatively common such division.[108] It should, however, be kept in mind that many of the positions in the ordering are still highly disputed, and also that the very notion that Plato's dialogues can or should be "ordered" is by no means universally accepted. Among those who classify the dialogues into periods of composition, Socrates figures in all of the "early dialogues" and they are considered the most faithful representations of the historical Socrates.[109] They include The Apology of Socrates, Charmides, Crito, Euthyphro, Ion, Laches, Lesser Hippias, Lysis, Menexenus, and Protagoras (often considered one of the last of the "early dialogues"). Three dialogues are often considered "transitional" or "pre-middle": Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Meno. Whereas those classified as "early dialogues" often conclude in aporia, the so-called "middle dialogues" provide more clearly stated positive teachings that are often ascribed to Plato such as the theory of Forms. These dialogues include Cratylus, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Republic, Symposium, Parmenides, and Theaetetus. Proponents of dividing the dialogues into periods often consider the Parmenides and Theaetetus to come late in this period and be transitional to the next, as they seem to treat the theory of Forms critically (Parmenides) or only indirectly (Theaetetus).[110] Ritter's stylometric analysis places Phaedrus as probably after Theaetetus and Parmenides,[111] although it does not relate to the theory of Forms in the same way. The first book of the Republic is often thought to have been written significantly earlier than the rest of the work, although possibly having undergone revisions when the later books were attached to it.[110] The remaining dialogues are classified as "late" and are generally agreed to be difficult and challenging pieces of philosophy. This grouping is the only one proven by stylometric analysis.[105] While looked to for Plato's "mature" answers to the questions posed by his earlier works, those answers are difficult to discern. Some scholars[109] indicate that the theory of Forms is absent from the late dialogues, its having been refuted in the Parmenides, but there isn't total consensus that the Parmenides actually refutes the theory of Forms.[112] The so-called "late dialogues" include Critias, Laws, Philebus, Sophist, Statesman, and Timaeus.[109] Narration of the dialogues Plato never presents himself as a participant in any of the dialogues, and with the exception of the Apology, there is no suggestion that he heard any of the dialogues firsthand. Some dialogues have no narrator but have a pure "dramatic" form (examples: Meno, Gorgias, Phaedrus, Crito, Euthyphro), some dialogues are narrated by Socrates, wherein he speaks in first person (examples: Lysis, Charmides, Republic). One dialogue, Protagoras, begins in dramatic form but quickly proceeds to Socrates' narration of a conversation he had previously with the sophist for whom the dialogue is named; this narration continues uninterrupted till the dialogue's end. Painting of a scene from Plato's Symposium (Anselm Feuerbach, 1873) Two dialogues Phaedo and Symposium also begin in dramatic form but then proceed to virtually uninterrupted narration by followers of Socrates. Phaedo, an account of Socrates' final conversation and hemlock drinking, is narrated by Phaedo to Echecrates in a foreign city not long after the execution took place.[113] The Symposium is narrated by Apollodorus, a Socratic disciple, apparently to Glaucon. Apollodorus assures his listener that he is recounting the story, which took place when he himself was an infant, not from his own memory, but as remembered by Aristodemus, who told him the story years ago. The Theaetetus is a peculiar case: a dialogue in dramatic form embedded within another dialogue in dramatic form. In the beginning of the Theaetetus (142c–143b), Euclides says that he compiled the conversation from notes he took based on what Socrates told him of his conversation with the title character. The rest of the Theaetetus is presented as a "book" written in dramatic form and read by one of Euclides' slaves (143c). Some scholars take this as an indication that Plato had by this date wearied of the narrated form.[114] With the exception of the Theaetetus, Plato gives no explicit indication as to how these orally transmitted conversations came to be written down. Trial of Socrates Main article: Trial of Socrates The trial of Socrates is the central, unifying event of Plato's dialogues. Because of this, Apology is among the most frequently read of his works. In the Apology, Socrates tries to dismiss rumors that he is a sophist and defends himself against charges of disbelief in the gods and corruption of the young. Socrates insists that long-standing slander will be the real cause of his demise, and says the legal charges are essentially false. Socrates famously denies being wise, and explains how his life as a philosopher was launched by the Oracle at Delphi. He says that his quest to resolve the riddle of the oracle put him at odds with his fellow man, and that this is the reason he has been mistaken for a menace to the city-state of Athens. If Plato's important dialogues do not refer to Socrates' execution explicitly, they allude to it, or use characters or themes that play a part in it. Five dialogues foreshadow the trial: In the Theaetetus (210d) and the Euthyphro (2a–b) Socrates tells people that he is about to face corruption charges. In the Meno (94e–95a), one of the men who brings legal charges against Socrates, Anytus, warns him about the trouble he may get into if he does not stop criticizing important people. In the Gorgias, Socrates says that his trial will be like a doctor prosecuted by a cook who asks a jury of children to choose between the doctor's bitter medicine and the cook's tasty treats (521e–522a). In the Republic (7.517e), Socrates explains why an enlightened man (presumably himself) will stumble in a courtroom situation. The Apology is Socrates' defense speech, and the Crito and Phaedo take place in prison after the conviction. In the Protagoras, Socrates is a guest at the home of Callias, son of Hipponicus, a man whom Socrates disparages in the Apology as having wasted a great amount of money on sophists' fees. Unity and diversity of the dialogues Two other important dialogues, the Symposium and the Phaedrus, are linked to the main storyline by characters. In the Apology (19b, c), Socrates says Aristophanes slandered him in a comic play, and blames him for causing his bad reputation, and ultimately, his death. In the Symposium, the two of them are drinking together with other friends. The character Phaedrus is linked to the main story line by character (Phaedrus is also a participant in the Symposium and the Protagoras) and by theme (the philosopher as divine emissary, etc.) The Protagoras is also strongly linked to the Symposium by characters: all of the formal speakers at the Symposium (with the exception of Aristophanes) are present at the home of Callias in that dialogue. Charmides and his guardian Critias are present for the discussion in the Protagoras. Examples of characters crossing between dialogues can be further multiplied. The Protagoras contains the largest gathering of Socratic associates. In the dialogues Plato is most celebrated and admired for, Socrates is concerned with human and political virtue, has a distinctive personality, and friends and enemies who "travel" with him from dialogue to dialogue. This is not to say that Socrates is consistent: a man who is his friend in one dialogue may be an adversary or subject of his mockery in another. For example, Socrates praises the wisdom of Euthyphro many times in the Cratylus, but makes him look like a fool in the Euthyphro. He disparages sophists generally, and Prodicus specifically in the Apology, whom he also slyly jabs in the Cratylus for charging the hefty fee of fifty drachmas for a course on language and grammar. However, Socrates tells Theaetetus in his namesake dialogue that he admires Prodicus and has directed many pupils to him. Socrates' ideas are also not consistent within or between or among dialogues. Platonic scholarship "The safest general characterisation of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato." (Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality, 1929). Although their popularity has fluctuated over the years, the works of Plato have never been without readers since the time they were written.[115] Plato's thought is often compared with that of his most famous student, Aristotle, whose reputation during the Western Middle Ages so completely eclipsed that of Plato that the Scholastic philosophers referred to Aristotle as "the Philosopher". However, in the Byzantine Empire, the study of Plato continued. The only Platonic work known to western scholarship was Timaeus, until translations were made at a time post the fall of Constantinople, which occurred during 1453,[116] George Gemistos Plethon brought Plato's original writings from Constantinople in the century of its fall. It is believed that Plethon passed a copy of the Dialogues to Cosimo de' Medici when in 1438 the Council of Ferrara, called to unify the Greek and Latin Churches, was adjourned to Florence, where Plethon then lectured on the relation and differences of Plato and Aristotle, and fired Cosimo with his enthusiasm;[117] Cosimo would supply Marsilio Ficino with Plato's text for translation to Latin. During the early Islamic era, Persian and Arab scholars translated much of Plato into Arabic and wrote commentaries and interpretations on Plato's, Aristotle's and other Platonist philosophers' works (see Al-Farabi, Avicenna, Averroes, Hunayn ibn Ishaq). Many of these comments on Plato were translated from Arabic into Latin and as such influenced Medieval scholastic philosophers.[118] During the Renaissance, with the general resurgence of interest in classical civilization, knowledge of Plato's philosophy would become widespread again in the West. Many of the greatest early modern scientists and artists who broke with Scholasticism and fostered the flowering of the Renaissance, with the support of the Plato-inspired Lorenzo (grandson of Cosimo), saw Plato's philosophy as the basis for progress in the arts and sciences. His political views, too, were well-received: the vision of wise philosopher-kings of the Republic matched the views set out in works such as Machiavelli's The Prince. More problematic was Plato's belief in metempsychosis, transmigration of the soul, as well as his ethical views (on polyamory and euthanasia in particular), which did not match those of Christianity. It was Plethon's student Bessarion who reconciled Plato with Christian theology, arguing that Plato's views were only ideals, unattainable due to the fall of man.[119] By the 19th century, Plato's reputation was restored, and at least on par with Aristotle's. Notable Western philosophers have continued to draw upon Plato's work since that time. Plato's influence has been especially strong in mathematics and the sciences. He helped to distinguish between pure and applied mathematics by widening the gap between "arithmetic", now called number theory and "logistic", now called arithmetic. He regarded "logistic" as appropriate for business men and men of war who "must learn the art of numbers or he will not know how to array his troops," while "arithmetic" was appropriate for philosophers "because he has to arise out of the sea of change and lay hold of true being."[120] Plato's resurgence further inspired some of the greatest advances in logic since Aristotle, primarily through Gottlob Frege and his followers Kurt Gödel, Alonzo Church, and Alfred Tarski. Albert Einstein suggested that the scientist who takes philosophy seriously would have to avoid systematization and take on many different roles, and possibly appear as a Platonist or Pythagorean, in that such a one would have "the viewpoint of logical simplicity as an indispensable and effective tool of his research."[121] Many recent philosophers have diverged from what some would describe as the ontological models and moral ideals characteristic of traditional Platonism. A number of these postmodern philosophers have thus appeared to disparage Platonism from more or less informed perspectives. Friedrich Nietzsche notoriously attacked Plato's "idea of the good itself" along with many fundamentals of Christian morality, which he interpreted as "Platonism for the masses" in one of his most important works, Beyond Good and Evil (1886). Martin Heidegger argued against Plato's alleged obfuscation of Being in his incomplete tome, Being and Time (1927), and the philosopher of science Karl Popper argued in The Open Society and Its Enemies (1945) that Plato's alleged proposal for a utopian political regime in the Republic was prototypically totalitarian. The political philosopher and professor Leo Strauss is considered by some as the prime thinker involved in the recovery of Platonic thought in its more political, and less metaphysical, form. Strauss' political approach was in part inspired by the appropriation of Plato and Aristotle by medieval Jewish and Islamic political philosophers, especially Maimonides and Al-Farabi, as opposed to the Christian metaphysical tradition that developed from Neoplatonism. Deeply influenced by Nietzsche and Heidegger, Strauss nonetheless rejects their condemnation of Plato and looks to the dialogues for a solution to what all three latter day thinkers acknowledge as 'the crisis of the West.' Textual sources and history First page of the Euthyphro, from the Clarke Plato (Codex Oxoniensis Clarkianus 39), 895 AD. The text is Greek minuscule. See also: List of manuscripts of Plato's dialogues Some 250 known manuscripts of Plato survive.[122] The texts of Plato as received today apparently represent the complete written philosophical work of Plato and are generally good by the standards of textual criticism.[123] No modern edition of Plato in the original Greek represents a single source, but rather it is reconstructed from multiple sources which are compared with each other. These sources are medieval manuscripts written on vellum (mainly from 9th-13th century AD Byzantium), papyri (mainly from late antiquity in Egypt), and from the independent testimonia of other authors who quote various segments of the works (which come from a variety of sources). The text as presented is usually not much different from what appears in the Byzantine manuscripts, and papyri and testimonia just confirm the manuscript tradition. In some editions however the readings in the papyri or testimonia are favoured in some places by the editing critic of the text. Reviewing editions of papyri for the Republic in 1987, Slings suggests that the use of papyri is hampered due to some poor editing practices.[124] In the first century AD, Thrasyllus of Mendes had compiled and published the works of Plato in the original Greek, both genuine and spurious. While it has not survived to the present day, all the extant medieval Greek manuscripts are based on his edition.[125] The oldest surviving complete manuscript for many of the dialogues is the Clarke Plato (Codex Oxoniensis Clarkianus 39, or Codex Boleianus MS E.D. Clarke 39), which was written in Constantinople in 895 and acquired by Oxford University in 1809.[126] The Clarke is given the siglum B in modern editions. B contains the first six tetralogies and is described internally as being written by "John the Calligrapher" on behalf of Arethas of Caesarea. It appears to have undergone corrections by Arethas himself.[127] For the last two tetralogies and the apocrypha, the oldest surviving complete manuscript is Codex Parisinus graecus 1807, designated A, which was written nearly contemporaneously to B, circa 900 AD.[128] A must be a copy of the edition edited by the patriarch, Photios, teacher of Arethas.[129][130][131]A probably had an initial volume containing the first 7 tetralogies which is now lost, but of which a copy was made, Codex Venetus append. class. 4, 1, which has the siglum T. The oldest manuscript for the seventh tetralogy is Codex Vindobonensis 54. suppl. phil. Gr. 7, with siglum W, with a supposed date in the twelfth century.[132] In total there are fifty-one such Byzantine manuscripts known, while others may yet be found.[133] To help establish the text, the older evidence of papyri and the independent evidence of the testimony of commentators and other authors (i.e., those who quote and refer to an old text of Plato which is no longer extant) are also used. Many papyri which contain fragments of Plato's texts are among the Oxyrhynchus Papyri. The 2003 Oxford Classical Texts edition by Slings even cites the Coptic translation of a fragment of the Republic in the Nag Hammadi library as evidence.[134] Important authors for testimony include Olympiodorus the Younger, Plutarch, Proclus, Iamblichus, Eusebius, and Stobaeus. During the early Renaissance, the Greek language and, along with it, Plato's texts were reintroduced to Western Europe by Byzantine scholars. In September or October 1484 Filippo Valori and Francesco Berlinghieri printed 1025 copies of Ficino's translation, using the printing press at the Dominican convent S.Jacopo di Ripoli.[135][136] Cosimo had been influenced toward studying Plato by the many Byzantine Platonists in Florence during his day, including George Gemistus Plethon. The 1578 edition [137] of Plato's complete works published by Henricus Stephanus (Henri Estienne) in Geneva also included parallel Latin translation and running commentary by Joannes Serranus (Jean de Serres). It was this edition which established standard Stephanus pagination, still in use today.[138] Modern editions The Oxford Classical Texts offers the current standard complete Greek text of Plato's complete works. In five volumes edited by John Burnet, its first edition was published 1900-1907, and it is still available from the publisher, having last been printed in 1993.[139][140] The second edition is still in progress with only the first volume, printed in 1995, and the Republic, printed in 2003, available. The Cambridge Greek and Latin Texts and Cambridge Classical Texts and Commentaries series includes Greek editions of the Protagoras, Symposium, Phaedrus, Alcibiades, and Clitophon, with English philological, literary, and, to an extent, philosophical commentary.[141][142] One distinguished edition of the Greek text is E. R. Dodds' of the Gorgias, which includes extensive English commentary.[143][144] The modern standard complete English edition is the 1997 Hackett Plato, Complete Works, edited by John M. Cooper.[145][146] For many of these translations Hackett offers separate volumes which include more by way of commentary, notes, and introductory material. There is also the Clarendon Plato Series by Oxford University Press which offers English translations and thorough philosophical commentary by leading scholars on a few of Plato's works, including John McDowell's version of the Theaetetus.[147] Cornell University Press has also begun the Agora series of English translations of classical and medieval philosophical texts, including a few of Plato's.[148]


Plato in arts Besides busts, sculptors - often idealized, several of Plato's Academy mosaic, were created in the villa of T. Siminius Stephanus in Pompeii, around 100 BC to 100 CE. The School of Athens fresco by Raphael features Plato also as a central figure.


See also Philosophy portal Cambridge Platonists List of speakers in Plato's dialogues Plato's Problem Plato's unwritten doctrines Platonic love Platonic solid Ellen Francis Mason, translator of Plato Allegorical interpretations of Plato Harold F. Cherniss, major Plato scholar Archestratus of Phrearrhi, Plato’s next door neighbour


Notes a. ^ Plato is a nickname from the adjective πλατύς platýs "broad". Diogenes Laertius mentions three possible meanings of the nickname:[149] ἐγυμνάσατο δὲ παρὰ Ἀρίστωνι τῷ Ἀργείῳ παλαιστῇ· ἀφ' οὗ καὶ Πλάτων διὰ τὴν εὐεξίαν μετωνομάσθη, πρότερον Ἀριστοκλῆς ἀπὸ τοῦ πάππου καλούμενος [ὄνομα], καθά φησιν Ἀλέξανδρος ἐν Διαδοχαῖς. ἔνιοι δὲ διὰ τὴν πλατύτητα τῆς ἑρμηνείας οὕτως ὀνομασθῆναι· ἢ ὅτι πλατὺς ἦν τὸ μέτωπον, ὥς φησι Νεάνθης. "And he learnt gymnastics under Ariston, the Argive wrestler. And from him he received the name of Plato on account of his robust figure, in place of his original name which was Aristocles, after his grandfather, as Alexander informs us in his Successions of Philosophers. But others affirm that he got the name Plato from the breadth of his style, or from the breadth of his forehead, as suggested by Neanthes." Seneca mentions the meaning of Plato's name in connection to a moral lesson:[150] Illud simul cogitemus, si mundum ipsum, non minus mortalem quam nos sumus, providentia periculis eximit, posse aliquatenus nostra quoque providentia longiorem prorogari huic corpusculo moram, si voluptates, quibus pars maior perit, potuerimus regere et coercere. Plato ipse ad senectutem se diligentia protulit. Erat quidem corpus validum ac forte sortitus et illi nomen latitudo pectoris fecerat, sed navigationes ac pericula multum detraxerant viribus; parsimonia tamen et eorum quae aviditatem evocant modus et diligens sui tutela perduxit illum ad senectutem multis prohibentibus causis. "Let us at the same time reflect, seeing that Providence rescues from its perils the world itself, which is no less mortal than we ourselves, that to some extent our petty bodies can be made to tarry longer upon earth by our own providence, if only we acquire the ability to control and check those pleasures whereby the greater portion of mankind perishes. Plato himself, by taking pains, advanced to old age. To be sure, he was the fortunate possessor of a strong and sound body (his very name was given him because of his broad chest); but his strength was much impaired by sea voyages and desperate adventures. Nevertheless, by frugal living, by setting a limit upon all that rouses the appetites, and by painstaking attention to himself, he reached that advanced age in spite of many hindrances." b. ^ The grammarian Apollodorus of Athens argues in his Chronicles that Plato was born in the first year of the eighty-eighth Olympiad (427 BC), on the seventh day of the month Thargelion; according to this tradition the god Apollo was born this day.[151] According to another biographer of him, Neanthes, Plato was eighty-four years of age at his death.[151] If we accept Neanthes' version, Plato was younger than Isocrates by six years, and therefore he was born in the second year of the 87th Olympiad, the year Pericles died (429 BC).[152] According to the Suda, Plato was born in Aegina in the 88th Olympiad amid the preliminaries of the Peloponnesian war, and he lived 82 years.[153] Sir Thomas Browne also believes that Plato was born in the 88th Olympiad.[154] Renaissance Platonists celebrated Plato's birth on November 7.[155] Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff estimates that Plato was born when Diotimos was archon eponymous, namely between July 29, 428 BC and July 24, 427 BC.[156] Greek philologist Ioannis Kalitsounakis believes that the philosopher was born on May 26 or 27, 427 BC, while Jonathan Barnes regards 428 BC as year of Plato's birth.[6][157] For her part, Debra Nails asserts that the philosopher was born in 424/423 BC.[155] According to Seneca Plato died at the age of 81 on the same day he was born.[158] c. ^ Diogenes Laertius mentions that Plato "was born, according to some writers, in Aegina in the house of Phidiades the son of Thales". Diogenes mentions as one of his sources the Universal History of Favorinus. According to Favorinus, Ariston, Plato's family, and his family were sent by Athens to settle as cleruchs (colonists retaining their Athenian citizenship), on the island of Aegina, from which they were expelled by the Spartans after Plato's birth there.[159] Nails points out, however, that there is no record of any Spartan expulsion of Athenians from Aegina between 431–411 BC.[160] On the other hand, at the Peace of Nicias, Aegina was silently left under Athens' control, and it was not until the summer of 411 that the Spartans overran the island.[161] Therefore, Nails concludes that "perhaps Ariston was a cleruch, perhaps he went to Aegina in 431, and perhaps Plato was born on Aegina, but none of this enables a precise dating of Ariston's death (or Plato's birth).[160] Aegina is regarded as Plato's place of birth by Suda as well.[153] d. ^ Some Wikipedia editors use the term allegory instead of myth. This is in accordance with the practice in the specialized literature, in which it is common to find that the terms allegory and myth are used as synonyms. Nevertheless, there is a trend among modern scholars to use the term myth and avoid the term allegory, as it is considered more appropriate to modern interpretation of Plato's writings. One of the first to initiate this trend was the Oxford University professor John Alexander Stewart, in his work The Myths of Plato.


Citations ^ Jones 2006. ^ "...the subject of philosophy, as it is often conceived—a rigorous and systematic examination of ethical, political, metaphysical, and epistemological issues, armed with a distinctive method—can be called his invention" (Kraut, Richard (11 September 2013). Zalta, Edward N., ed. "Plato". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Retrieved 3 April 2014. ) ^ Cooper, John M.; Hutchinson, D. S., eds. (1997): "Introduction". ^ "The Oldest Surviving Manuscript of Plato's Tetralogies", historyofinformation.co, accessed June 5, 2017: http://www.historyofinformation.com/expanded.php?id=1880. ^ Brumbaugh, Robert Sherrick, "Plato for the Modern Age", University Press of America: Lanham, Maryland (1991), 199, https://books.google.com/books?id=If5YWCbJhHoC&lpg=PA199&dq=oldest%20complete%20extant%20m&pg=PA199#v=onepage&q&f=false. ^ a b Plato at Encyclopædia Britannica ^ Whitehead 1978, p. 39. ^ Michel Foucault, The Hermeneutics of the Subject ^ "Though influenced primarily by Socrates, to the extent that Socrates is usually the main character in many of Plato's writings, he was also influenced by Heraclitus, Parmenides, and the Pythagoreans" (http://www.iep.utm.edu/plato/). ^ Kraut, Richard (11 September 2013). Zalta, Edward N., ed. "Plato". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Retrieved 3 April 2014.  ^ Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, III • Nails 2002, p. 53 • Wilamowitz-Moellendorff 2005, p. 46 ^ Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, I ^ a b Guthrie 1986, p. 10 • Taylor 2001, p. xiv • Wilamowitz-Moellendorff 2005, p. 47 ^ Plato, Republic 368a • Wilamowitz-Moellendorff 2005, p. 47 ^ According to James Adam, some have held that "Glaucon and Adeimantus were uncles of Plato, but Zeller decides for the usual view that they were brothers" (source). ^ Xenophon, Memorabilia, 3.6.1 ^ Nails 2002, p. 247. ^ Nails 2002, p. 246. ^ Apuleius, De Dogmate Platonis, 1 • Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, I • "Plato". Suda.  ^ Cicero, De Divinatione, I, 36 ^ Nails 2002, p. 53 • Taylor 2001, p. xiv ^ Plato, Charmides 158a • Nails 2003, pp. 228–229 ^ Plato, Charmides 158a • Plutarch, Pericles, IV ^ Plato, Gorgias 481d and Gorgias 513b • Aristophanes, Wasps, 97 ^ Plato, Parmenides 126c ^ Guthrie 1986, p. 11. ^ Kahn 2004, p. 186. ^ Laërtius 1925, § 4. ^ a b David Sedley, Plato's Cratylus, Cambridge University Press 2003, pp. 21–22. ^ Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, IV ^ Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, IV • Notopoulos 1939, p. 135 ^ a b see Tarán 1981, p. 226. ^ Guthrie 1986, p. 12 (footnote). ^ Apuleius, De Dogmate Platonis, 2 ^ Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, IV • Smith 1870, p. 393 ^ Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, V ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1.987a ^ Craig, Edward (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. p. 432. ISBN 0415073103.  ^ Jeremiah’s ministry was active from the thirteenth year of Josiah, king of Judah (3298 HC, 463 BCE, until after the fall of Jerusalem and the destruction of Solomon’s Temple in 403 BCE (3358 HC.[original research?] ^ Torath Ha'ola (http://hebrewbooks.org/11920, Rabbi Meir Isserles, p. Prague 1570 ch. 1, par. 11. Seder HaDoroth year 3300 (HC). Ma'var Yabok (A. Berekiah), ch. 33 p. 234 ^ McEvoy 1984. ^ Cairns 1961, p. xiii. ^ Robinson 1827, p. 16. ^ Dillon 2003, pp. 1–3. ^ Press 2000, p. 1. ^ Riginos 1976, p. 73. ^ Not to be confused with Anniceris the Cyrenaic philosopher. ^ Diogenes Laertius, Book iii, 20 ^ Riginos 1976, p. 194. ^ Schall 1996. ^ a b Riginos 1976, p. 195. ^ R.M. Hare, Plato in C.C.W. Taylor, R.M. Hare and Jonathan Barnes, Greek Philosophers, Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999 (1982), 103–189, here 117–9. ^ Russell, Bertrand (1991). History of Western Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 120–124. ISBN 0-415-07854-7.  ^ a b c McFarlane, Thomas J. "Plato's Parmenides". Integralscience. Retrieved 12 February 2017.  ^ Metaphysics, 1.6.1 (987a) ^ Tusc. Disput. 1.17.39. ^ George Karamanolis (2013). "Numenius". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  ^ a b Large, William. "Heraclitus". Arasite. Retrieved 3 March 2017.  ^ John Palmer. "Parmenides". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  ^ Strauss 1964, pp. 50–51. ^ Chappel, Timothy. "Mythos and Logos in Plato". Open University. Retrieved 20 August 2017.  ^ Edelstein, Ludwig (October 1949). "The Function of the Myth in Plato's Philosophy". Journal of the History of Ideas. X (4): 463–481.  ^ Partenie, Catalin. "Plato's Myths". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 29 October 2017.  ^ Baird & Kaufmann 2008. ^ "Plato's The Allegory of the Cave: Meaning and Interpretation". Bachelor and Master. Retrieved February 25, 2017.  ^ Fine 2003, p. 5. ^ McDowell 1973, p. 230. ^ Fine 1979, p. 366. ^ McDowell 1973, p. 256. ^ Taylor 2011, pp. 176–187. ^ Lee 2011, p. 432. ^ Taylor 2011, p. 189. ^ Blössner 2007, pp. 345–349. ^ Plato, Timaeus 44d & Timaeus 70 ^ Dorter 2006, p. 360. ^ Plato, Republic 488 ^ a b Blössner 2007, p. 350. ^ Republic 550b ^ Republic 554a ^ Republic 561a–b ^ Republic 571a ^ Dorter 2006, pp. 253–267. ^ Rodriguez-Grandjean 1998. ^ Reale 1990. Cf. p. 14 and onwards. ^ Krämer 1990. Cf. pp. 38–47. ^ Elementa harmonica II, 30–31; quoted in Gaiser 1980, p. 5. ^ Plotinus describes this in the last part of his final Ennead (VI, 9) entitled On the Good, or the One (Περὶ τἀγαθοῦ ἢ τοῦ ἑνός). Jens Halfwassen states in Der Aufstieg zum Einen' (2006) that "Plotinus' ontology—which should be called Plotinus' henology—is a rather accurate philosophical renewal and continuation of Plato's unwritten doctrine, i.e. the doctrine rediscovered by Krämer and Gaiser." ^ In one of his letters (Epistolae 1612) Ficino writes: "The main goal of the divine Plato ... is to show one principle of things, which he called the One (τὸ ἕν)", cf. Montoriola 1926, p. 147. ^ Gomperz 1931. ^ Gaiser 1998. ^ For a brief description of the problem see for example Gaiser 1980. A more detailed analysis is given by Krämer 1990. Another description is by Reale 1997 and Reale 1990. A thorough analysis of the consequences of such an approach is given by Szlezak 1999. Another supporter of this interpretation is the German philosopher Karl Albert, cf. Albert 1980 or Albert 1996. Hans-Georg Gadamer is also sympathetic towards it, cf. Grondin 2010 and Gadamer 1980. Gadamer's final position on the subject is stated in Gadamer 1997. ^ a b Blackburn 1996, p. 104. ^ Hartz, Louis. 1984. A Synthesis of World History. Zurich: Humanity Press ^ Popper 1962, p. 133. ^ CDC Reeve (Delta Kappa Epsilon Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill), A Plato Reader: Eight Essential Dialogues (p. vi), Hackett Publishing, 2012 ISBN 1603849173. ^ Robin Barrow (Professor of Philosophy of Education at Simon Fraser University, Canada and Fellow of The Royal Society of Canada), Plato: Appendix 2: Notes on the authenticity and Groupings of Plato's works, Bloomsbury Publishing, 2014 ISBN 1472504852. ^ Platonic Writings/Platonic Readings (page x) (edited by CL Griswold Jr), Penn State Press, 2010 ISBN 0271044810. ^ JM Cooper (Stuart Professor of Philosophy, Princeton University, 1997); DS Hutchinson, Complete Works (p. xii), Hackett Publishing, 1997. ^ H Tarrant (Professor of Classics at the University of Newcastle, New South Wales), Plato's First Interpreters, Cornell University Press, 2000 ISBN 080143792X. ^ B Jowett, Menexenus: Appendix I (1st paragraph). ^ The extent to which scholars consider a dialogue to be authentic is noted in Cooper 1997, pp. v–vi. ^ Bloom 1982, p. 5. ^ Burnet 1928b, p. 9. ^ Aristotle, Politics 1264b24-27. ^ a b Cooper 1997, p. xiv. ^ Kraut 2013; Schofield 2002; and Rowe 2006. ^ Brickhouse & Smith. ^ See Guthrie 1986; Vlastos 1991; Penner 1992; Kahn 1996; Fine 1999b. ^ a b c Dodds 2004. ^ a b Brandwood 1990, p. 251. ^ Brandwood 1990, p. 77. ^ Meinwald 1991. ^ "The time is not long after the death of Socrates; for the Pythagoreans [Echecrates & co.] have not heard any details yet" (Burnet 1911, p. 5). ^ Burnet 1928a, §177. ^ Cooper 1997, p. vii. ^ C. U. M. Smith - Brain, Mind and Consciousness in the History of Neuroscience (page 1) Springer Science & Business, 1 Jan 2014, 374 pages, Volume 6 of History, philosophy and theory of the life sciences SpringerLink : Bücher ISBN 9401787743 [Retrieved 2015-06-27] ^ Lackner 2001, p. 21. ^ See Burrell 1998 and Hasse 2002, pp. 33–45. ^ Harris, Jonathan (2002). "Byzantines in Renaissance Italy". ORB: The Online Reference Book for Medieval Studies. College of Staten Island, City University of New York. Retrieved 9 February 2015. [permanent dead link] ^ Boyer 1991, p. 86: 'Plato is important in the history of mathematics largely for his role as inspirer and director of others, and perhaps to him is due the sharp distinction in ancient Greece between arithmetic (in the sense of the theory of numbers) and logistic (the technique of computation). Plato regarded logistic as appropriate for the businessman and for the man of war, who "must learn the art of numbers or he will not know how to array his troops." The philosopher, on the other hand, must be an arithmetician "because he has to arise out of the sea of change and lay hold of true being."' ^ Einstein 1949, pp. 683–684. ^ Brumbaugh & Wells 1989. ^ Irwin 2011, pp. 64 & 74. See also Slings 1987, p. 34: "... primary MSS. together offer a text of tolerably good quality" (this is without the further corrections of other sources). ^ Slings 1987, p. 31. ^ Cooper 1997, pp. viii–xii. ^ "Manuscripts – Philosophy Faculty Library". 2 March 2012. Archived from the original on 2 March 2012. CS1 maint: BOT: original-url status unknown (link) ^ Dodds 1959, pp. 35–36. ^ Dodds 1959, p. 37. ^ RD McKirahan, Philosophy Before Socrates: An Introduction with Texts and Commentary (2nd ed.), Hackett Publishing, 2011, p. 1 ISBN 1603846123. ^ RS Brumbaugh, Plato for the Modern Age (p. 199), University Press of America, 1991 ISBN 0819183563. ^ J Duffy Byzantine Philosophy and Its Ancient Sources: "The lonely mission of Michael Psellos" edited by K Ierodiakonou (Oxford University Press, 2004) ISBN 0199269718. ^ Dodds 1959, p. 39. ^ Irwin 2011, p. 71. ^ Slings 2003, p. xxiii. ^ J Hankins, Plato in the Italian Renaissance Vol. 1 (p. 300), BRILL, 1990 ISBN 9004091610. ^ Allen 1975, p. 12. ^ Platonis opera quae extant omnia edidit Henricus Stephanus, Genevae, 1578. ^ Suzanne 2009. ^ Cooper 1997, pp. xii & xxvii. ^ Oxford Classical Texts – Classical Studies & Ancient History Series. Oxford University Press ^ Cambridge Greek and Latin Classics – Series. Cambridge University Press ^ Cambridge Classical Texts and Commentaries. Cambridge University Press ^ Irwin 1979, pp. vi & 11. ^ Dodds 1959. ^ Fine 1999a, p. 482. ^ Complete Works – Philosophy ^ Clarendon Plato Series – Philosophy Series. Oxford University Press ^ Cornell University Press : Agora Editions ^ Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, 3.4; translation by Robert Drew Hicks ^ Seneca, Epistulae, VI 58:29-30; translation by Robert Mott Gummere ^ a b Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, II ^ Nietzsche 1967, p. 32. ^ a b "Plato". Suda.  ^ Browne 1672. ^ a b Nails 2006, p. 1. ^ Wilamowitz-Moellendorff 2005, p. 46. ^ "Plato". Encyclopaedic Dictionary The Helios Volume V (in Greek). 1952.  ^ Seneca, Epistulae, VI, 58, 31: natali suo decessit et annum umum atque octogensimum. ^ Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, III ^ a b Nails 2002, p. 54. ^ Thucydides, 5.18 • Thucydides, 8.92


References Primary sources (Greek and Roman) Apuleius, De Dogmate Platonis, I. See original text in Latin Library. Aristophanes, The Wasps. See original text in Perseus program. Aristotle, Metaphysics. See original text in Perseus program. Cicero, De Divinatione, I. See original text in Latin library.  Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). "Plato". Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. 1:3. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.  Plato.  Charmides. Jowett, Benjamin (translator). Wikisource.  See original text in Perseus program. Plato.  Gorgias. Jowett Benjamin (translator). Wikisource.  See original text in Perseus program. Plato (1903). Parmenides. Translated by Burnet, John. Oxford University.  republished by: Crane, Gregory (ed.). "Perseus Digital Library Project".  Plato.  The Republic. Jowett Benjamin (translator). Wikisource.  See original text in Perseus program. Plutarch (1683) [written in the late 1st century]. " Pericles". Lives. Dryden, John (translator). Wikisource.  See original text in Perseus program. Seneca the Younger.  Moral Letters to Lucilius: Letter 58. Translated by Richard Mott Gummere. Wikisource.  See original text in Latin Library. Thucydides.  History of the Peloponnesian War. Crawley, Richard (translator). Wikisource. , V, VIII. See original text in Perseus program. Xenophon, Memorabilia. See original text in Perseus program. Secondary sources Albert, Karl (1980). Griechische Religion und platonische Philosophie. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.  Albert, Karl (1996). Einführung in die philosophische Mystik. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.  Allen, Michael J. B. (1975). "Introduction". Marsilio Ficino: The Philebus Commentary. University of California Press. pp. 1–58.  Baird, Forrest E.; Kaufmann, Walter, eds. (2008). Philosophic Classics: From Plato to Derrida (Fifth ed.). Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Pearson Prentice Hall. ISBN 0-13-158591-6.  Blackburn, Simon (1996). The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press.  Bloom, Harold (1982). Agon. Oxford: Oxford University Press.  Blössner, Norbert (2007). "The City-Soul Analogy". In Ferrari, G. R. F. The Cambridge Companion to Plato's Republic. Translated from the German by G. R. F. Ferrari. Cambridge University Press.  Borody, W. A. (1998). "Figuring the Phallogocentric Argument with Respect to the Classical Greek Philosophical Tradition". Nebula, A Netzine of the Arts and Science. 13: 1–27.  Boyer, Carl B. (1991). Merzbach, Uta C., ed. A History of Mathematics (Second ed.). John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 0-471-54397-7.  Brandwood, Leonard (1990). The Chronology of Plato's Dialogues. Cambridge University Press.  Brickhouse, Thomas; Smith, Nicholas D. Fieser, James; Dowden, Bradley, eds. "Plato". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 3 April 2014.  Browne, Sir Thomas (1672). "XII". Pseudodoxia Epidemica. IV (6th ed.).  Brumbaugh, Robert S.; Wells, Rulon S. (October 1989). "Completing Yale's Microfilm Project". The Yale University Library Gazette. 64 (1/2): 73–75. JSTOR 40858970.  Burnet, John (1911). Plato's Phaedo. Oxford University Press.  Burnet, John (1928a). Greek Philosophy: Part I: Thales to Plato. MacMillan.  Burnet, John (1928b). Platonism. University of California Press.  Cairns, Huntington (1961). "Introduction". In Hamilton, Edith; Cairns, Huntington. The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Including the Letters. Princeton University Press.  Burrell, David (1998). "Platonism in Islamic Philosophy". In Craig, Edward. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 7. Routledge. pp. 429–430.  Cooper, John M.; Hutchinson, D. S., eds. (1997). Plato: Complete Works. Hackett Publishing.  Dillon, John (2003). The Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy. Oxford University Press.  Dodds, E. R. (1959). Plato Gorgias. Oxford University Press.  Dodds, E. R. (2004) [1951]. The Greeks and the Irrational. University of California Press.  Dorter, Kenneth (2006). The Transformation of Plato's Republic. Lexington Books.  Einstein, Albert (1949). "Remarks to the Essays Appearing in this Collective Volume". In Schilpp. Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist. The Library of Living Philosophers. 7. MJF Books. pp. 663–688.  Fine, Gail (July 1979). "Knowledge and Logos in the Theaetetus". Philosophical Review. 88 (3).  Reprinted in Fine 2003. Fine, Gail (1999a). "Selected Bibliography". Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology. Oxford University Press. pp. 481–494.  Fine, Gail (1999b). "Introduction". Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion, and the Soul. Oxford University Press. pp. 1–33.  Fine, Gail (2003). "Introduction". Plato on Knowledge and Forms: Selected Essays. Oxford University Press.  Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1980) [1968]. "Plato's Unwritten Dialectic". Dialogue and Dialectic. Yale University Press. pp. 124–155.  Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1997). "Introduzione". In Girgenti, Giuseppe. La nuova interpretazione di Platone. Milan: Rusconi Libri.  Gaiser, Konrad (1980). "Plato's Enigmatic Lecture 'On the Good'". Phronesis. 25 (1): 5–37. doi:10.1163/156852880x00025.  Gaiser, Konrad (1998). Reale, Giovanni, ed. Testimonia Platonica: Le antiche testimonianze sulle dottrine non scritte di Platone. Milan: Vita e Pensiero.  First published as "Testimonia Platonica. Quellentexte zur Schule und mündlichen Lehre Platons" as an appendix to Gaiser's Platons Ungeschriebene Lehre, Stuttgart, 1963. Gomperz, H. (1931). "Plato's System of Philosophy". In Ryle, G. Proceedings of the Seventh International Congress of Philosophy. London. pp. 426–431.  Reprinted in Gomperz, H. (1953). Philosophical Studies. Boston: Christopher Publishing House 1953, pp. 119–24. Grondin, Jean (2010). "Gadamer and the Tübingen School". In Gill, Christopher; Renaud, François. Hermeneutic Philosophy and Plato: Gadamer's Response to the Philebus. Academia Verlag. pp. 139–156.  Guthrie, W.K.C. (1986). A History of Greek Philosophy: Volume 4, Plato: The Man and His Dialogues: Earlier Period. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-31101-2.  Hasse, Dag Nikolaus (2002). "Plato arabico-latinus". In Gersh; Hoenen. The Platonic Tradition in the Middle Ages: A Doxographic Approach. De Gruyter. pp. 33–66.  Irwin, T. H. (1979). Plato: Gorgias. Oxford University Press.  Irwin, T. H. (2011). "The Platonic Corpus". In Fine, G. The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford University Press.  Jones, Daniel (2006). Roach, Peter; Hartman, James; Setter, Jane, eds. Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary (17 ed.). Cambridge University Press.  Kahn, Charles H. (1996). Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-64830-0.  Kierkegaard, Søren (1992). "Plato". The Concept of Irony. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-02072-3.  Krämer, Hans Joachim (1990). Catan, John R., ed. Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics: A Work on the Theory of the Principles and Unwritten Doctrines of Plato with a Collection of the Fundamental Documents. State University of New York Press. ISBN 0-7914-0433-1.  Lee, M.-K. (2011). "The Theaetetus". In Fine, G. The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford University Press. pp. 411–436.  Kraut, Richard (11 September 2013). Zalta, Edward N., ed. "Plato". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Retrieved 3 April 2014.  Lackner, D. F. (2001). "The Camaldolese Academy: Ambrogio Traversari, Marsilio Ficino and the Christian Platonic Tradition". In Allen; Rees. Marsilio Ficino: His Theology, His Philosophy, His Legacy. Brill.  Meinwald, Constance Chu (1991). Plato's Parmenides. Oxford: Oxford University Press.  McDowell, J. (1973). Plato: Theaetetus. Oxford University Press.  McEvoy, James (1984). "Plato and The Wisdom of Egypt". Irish Philosophical Journal. Belfast: Dept. of Scholastic Philosophy, Queen's University of Belfast. 1 (2). ISSN 0266-9080. Archived from the original on 2007-12-05. Retrieved 2007-12-03.  Montoriola, Karl Markgraf von (1926). Briefe Des Mediceerkreises Aus Marsilio Ficino's Epistolarium. Berlin: Juncker.  Nails, Debra (2002). The People of Plato: A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics. Hackett Publishing. ISBN 0-87220-564-9.  Nails, Debra (2006). "The Life of Plato of Athens". In Benson, Hugh H. A Companion to Plato. Blackwell Publishing. ISBN 1-4051-1521-1.  Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm (1967). "Vorlesungsaufzeichnungen". Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe (in German). Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 3-11-013912-X.  Notopoulos, A. (April 1939). "The Name of Plato". Classical Philology. The University of Chicago Press. 34 (2): 135–145. doi:10.1086/362227.  Penner, Terry (1992). "Socrates and the Early Dialogues". In Kraut, Richard. The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge University Press. pp. 121–169.  Plato at Encyclopædia Britannica "Plato". Encyclopaedic Dictionary The Helios Volume XVI (in Greek). 1952.  "Plato". Suda. 10th century.  Popper, K. (1962). The Open Society and its Enemies. 1. London: Routledge.  Press, Gerald Alan (2000). "Introduction". In Press, Gerald Alan. Who Speaks for Plato?: Studies in Platonic Anonymity. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 1–14.  Reale, Giovanni (1990). Catan, John R., ed. Plato and Aristotle. A History of Ancient Philosophy. 2. State University of New York Press.  Reale, Giovanni (1997). Toward a New Interpretation of Plato. Washington, D.C.: CUA Press.  Riginos, Alice (1976). Platonica : the anecdotes concerning the life and writings of Plato. Leiden: E.J. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-04565-1.  Robinson, John (1827). Archæologica Græca (Second ed.). London: A. J. Valpy. Archived from the original on 2014-07-01. Retrieved 2017-02-04.  Rodriguez-Grandjean, Pablo (1998). Philosophy and Dialogue: Plato's Unwritten Doctrines from a Hermeneutical Point of View. Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy. Boston.  Rowe, Christopher (2006). "Interpreting Plato". In Benson, Hugh H. A Companion to Plato. Blackwell Publishing. pp. 13–24.  Schall, James V. (Summer 1996). "On the Death of Plato". The American Scholar. 65.  Schofield, Malcolm (23 August 2002). Craig, Edward, ed. "Plato". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. Archived from the original on 10 October 2008. Retrieved 3 April 2014.  Sedley, David (2003). Plato's Cratylus. Cambridge University Press.  Slings, S. R. (1987). "Remarks on Some Recent Papyri of the Politeia". Mnemosyne. Fourth. 40 (1/2): 27–34. doi:10.1163/156852587x00030.  Slings, S. R. (2003). Platonis Rempublicam. Oxford University Press.  Smith, William (1870). "Plato". Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology.  Strauss, Leo (1964). The City and the Man. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.  Suzanne, Bernard (8 March 2009). "The Stephanus edition". Plato and his dialogues. Retrieved 3 April 2014.  Szlezak, Thomas A. (1999). Reading Plato. Routledge. ISBN 0-415-18984-5.  Tarán, Leonardo (1981). Speusippus of Athens. Brill Publishers.  Tarán, Leonardo (2001). "Plato's Alleged Epitaph". Collected Papers 1962-1999. Brill Academic Publishers. ISBN 9004123040.  Taylor, Alfred Edward (2001) [1937]. Plato: The Man and His Work. Courier Dover Publications. ISBN 0-486-41605-4.  Taylor, C. C. W. (2011). "Plato's Epistemology". In Fine, G. The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford University Press. pp. 165–190.  Vlastos, Gregory (1991). Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Cambridge University Press.  Whitehead, Alfred North (1978). Process and Reality. New York: The Free Press.  Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Ulrich von (2005) [1917]. Plato: His Life and Work (translated in Greek by Xenophon Armyros). Kaktos. ISBN 960-382-664-2. 


Further reading Alican, Necip Fikri (2012). Rethinking Plato: A Cartesian Quest for the Real Plato. Amsterdam and New York: Editions Rodopi B.V. ISBN 978-90-420-3537-9.  Allen, R. E. (1965). Studies in Plato's Metaphysics II. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 0710036264 Ambuel, David (2007). Image and Paradigm in Plato's Sophist. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-04-9 Arieti, James A. Interpreting Plato: The Dialogues as Drama, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc. ISBN 0-8476-7662-5 Bakalis, Nikolaos (2005). Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments, Trafford Publishing ISBN 1-4120-4843-5 Barrow, Robin (2007). Plato: Continuum Library of Educational Thought. Continuum. ISBN 0-8264-8408-5.  Cadame, Claude (1999). Indigenous and Modern Perspectives on Tribal Initiation Rites: Education According to Plato, pp. 278–312, in Padilla, Mark William (editor), "Rites of Passage in Ancient Greece: Literature, Religion, Society", Bucknell University Press, 1999. ISBN 0-8387-5418-X Cooper, John M.; Hutchinson, D.S., eds. (1997). Plato: Complete Works. Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. ISBN 0-87220-349-2.  Corlett, J. Angelo (2005). Interpreting Plato's Dialogues. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-02-5 Durant, Will (1926). The Story of Philosophy. Simon & Schuster. ISBN 0-671-69500-2.  Derrida, Jacques (1972). La dissémination, Paris: Seuil. (esp. cap.: La Pharmacie de Platon, 69–199) ISBN 2-02-001958-2 Field, G. C. (1969). The Philosophy of Plato (2nd ed. with an appendix by Cross, R. C. ed.). London: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-888040-5.  Fine, Gail (2000). Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology Oxford University Press, US, ISBN 0-19-875206-7 Finley, M. I. (1969). Aspects of antiquity: Discoveries and Controversies The Viking Press, Inc., USA Garvey, James (2006). Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books. Continuum. ISBN 0-8264-9053-0.  Guthrie, W. K. C. (1986). A History of Greek Philosophy (Plato – The Man & His Dialogues – Earlier Period), Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-31101-2 Guthrie, W. K. C. (1986). A History of Greek Philosophy (Later Plato & the Academy) Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-31102-0 Havelock, Eric (2005). Preface to Plato (History of the Greek Mind), Belknap Press, ISBN 0-674-69906-8 Hamilton, Edith; Cairns, Huntington, eds. (1961). The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Including the Letters. Princeton Univ. Press. ISBN 0-691-09718-6.  Harvard University Press publishes the hardbound series Loeb Classical Library, containing Plato's works in Greek, with English translations on facing pages. Irvine, Andrew David (2008). Socrates on Trial: A play based on Aristophanes' Clouds and Plato's Apology, Crito, and Phaedo, adapted for modern performance. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.  ISBN 978-0-8020-9783-5 (cloth); ISBN 978-0-8020-9538-1 (paper) Hermann, Arnold (2010). Plato's Parmenides: Text, Translation & Introductory Essay, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-71-1 Irwin, Terence (1995). Plato's Ethics, Oxford University Press, USA, ISBN 0-19-508645-7 Jackson, Roy (2001). Plato: A Beginner's Guide. London: Hoder & Stroughton. ISBN 0-340-80385-1.  Jowett, Benjamin (1892). [The Dialogues of Plato. Translated into English with analyses and introductions by B. Jowett.], Oxford Clarendon Press, UK, UIN:BLL01002931898 Kochin, Michael S. (2002). Gender and Rhetoric in Plato's Political Thought. Cambridge Univ. Press. ISBN 0-521-80852-9.  Kraut, Richard, ed. (1993). The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-43610-9.  Lilar, Suzanne (1954), Journal de l'analogiste, Paris, Éditions Julliard; Reedited 1979, Paris, Grasset. Foreword by Julien Gracq Lilar, Suzanne (1963), Le couple, Paris, Grasset. Translated as Aspects of Love in Western Society in 1965, with a foreword by Jonathan Griffin London, Thames and Hudson. Lilar, Suzanne (1967) A propos de Sartre et de l'amour , Paris, Grasset. Lundberg, Phillip (2005). Tallyho - The Hunt for Virtue: Beauty, Truth and Goodness Nine Dialogues by Plato: Pheadrus, Lysis, Protagoras, Charmides, Parmenides, Gorgias, Theaetetus, Meno & Sophist. Authorhouse. ISBN 1-4184-4977-6.  Márquez, Xavier (2012) A Stranger's Knowledge: Statesmanship, Philosophy & Law in Plato's Statesman, Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-79-7 Melchert, Norman (2002). The Great Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy. McGraw Hill. ISBN 0-19-517510-7.  Miller, Mitchell (2004). The Philosopher in Plato's Statesman. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-16-2 Mohr, Richard D. (2006). God and Forms in Plato - and other Essays in Plato's Metaphysics. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-01-8 Mohr, Richard D. (Ed.), Sattler, Barbara M. (Ed.) (2010) One Book, The Whole Universe: Plato's Timaeus Today, Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-32-2 Moore, Edward (2007). Plato. Philosophy Insights Series. Tirril, Humanities-Ebooks. ISBN 978-1-84760-047-9 Nightingale, Andrea Wilson. (1995). "Genres in Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy", Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-48264-X Oxford University Press publishes scholarly editions of Plato's Greek texts in the Oxford Classical Texts series, and some translations in the Clarendon Plato Series. Patterson, Richard (Ed.), Karasmanis, Vassilis (Ed.), Hermann, Arnold (Ed.) (2013) Presocratics & Plato: Festschrift at Delphi in Honor of Charles Kahn, Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-75-9 Sallis, John (1996). Being and Logos: Reading the Platonic Dialogues. Indiana University Press. ISBN 0-253-21071-2.  Sallis, John (1999). Chorology: On Beginning in Plato's "Timaeus". Indiana University Press. ISBN 0-253-21308-8.  Sayre, Kenneth M. (2005). Plato's Late Ontology: A Riddle Resolved. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-09-4 Seung, T. K. (1996). Plato Rediscovered: Human Value and Social Order. Rowman and Littlefield. ISBN 0-8476-8112-2 Smith, William. (1867). Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology. University of Michigan/Online version.  Stewart, John. (2010). Kierkegaard and the Greek World – Socrates and Plato. Ashgate. ISBN 978-0-7546-6981-4 Thesleff, Holger (2009). Platonic Patterns: A Collection of Studies by Holger Thesleff, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-29-2 Thomas Taylor has translated Plato's complete works. Thomas Taylor (1804). The Works of Plato, viz. His Fifty-Five Dialogues and Twelve Epistles 5 vols Vlastos, Gregory (1981). Platonic Studies, Princeton University Press, ISBN 0-691-10021-7 Vlastos, Gregory (2006). Plato's Universe – with a new Introducution by Luc Brisson, Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-13-1 Zuckert, Catherine (2009). Plato's Philosophers: The Coherence of the Dialogues, The University of Chicago Press, ISBN 978-0-226-99335-5


External links English Wikisource has original text related to this article: Plato Greek Wikisource has original text related to this article: Platon Wikiquote has quotations related to: Plato Wikibooks has a book on the topic of: Plato Wikimedia Commons has media related to Plato. Works available on-line: Works by Plato at Perseus Project – Greek & English hyperlinked text Works of Plato (Jowett, 1892) Works by Plato at Project Gutenberg Works by or about Plato at Internet Archive Works by Plato at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks) Plato complete works, annotated and searchable, at ELPENOR Quick Links to Plato's Dialogues (English, Greek, French, Spanish) The Dialogues of Plato with Apocryphal Works from Loeb Classical Library edition (1925–1968) Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Plato Plato's Organicism Plato's Phaedo Plato's Political Philosophy Plato's Republic Plato's Theaetetus Plato's Academy Middle Platonism Neoplatonism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Plato Plato's Ethics Plato's Ethics and Politics in The Republic Friendship and Eros Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology Plato on Utopia Rhetoric and Poetry Other resources: Plato at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project Plato at PhilPapers  "Plato and Platonism". Catholic Encyclopedia. 1913.  Website on Plato and his works: Plato and his dialogues by Bernard Suzanne Approaching Plato: A Guide to the Early and Middle Dialogues v t e Plato Life Early life Platonism Platonic epistemology Platonic idealism Platonic realism Platonic love Neoplatonism and Gnosticism Platonism in the Renaissance Demiurge Theory of Forms Transcendentals Form of the Good Third man argument Euthyphro dilemma Five regimes Philosopher king Unwritten doctrines Cultural influence of Plato's Republic Works Uncontested Apology Charmides Cratylus Critias Crito Euthydemus Euthyphro First Alcibiades Gorgias Hippias Major Hippias Minor Ion Laches Papyrus Oxyrhynchus 228 Laws Papyrus Oxyrhynchus 23 Lysis Menexenus Meno Parmenides Phaedo Papyrus Oxyrhynchus 229 Phaedrus Philebus Protagoras Republic Sophist Statesman Symposium Theaetetus Timaeus Of doubtful authenticity Axiochus Clitophon Definitions Demodocus Epigrams Epinomis Epistles Letter I Letter II Letter V Letter VII Letter IX Letter X Letter XII Eryxias Halcyon Hipparchus Minos On Justice On Virtue Rival Lovers Second Alcibiades Sisyphus Theages Allegories and metaphors Atlantis Ring of Gyges The Cave The Divided Line The Sun Ship of State Myth of Er The Chariot Allegorical interpretations of Plato Related Commentaries The Academy in Athens Socratic problem Middle Platonism Neoplatonism and Christianity Poitier Meets Plato List of speakers in Plato's dialogues Plato's Dream Family Ariston of Athens (father) Pyrilampes (stepfather) Perictione (mother) Adeimantus of Collytus (brother) Glaucon (brother) Potone (sister) Speusippus (nephew) Articles related to Plato v t e Platonists Academics Old Plato Speusippus Heraclides Ponticus Menedemus of Pyrrha Eudoxus of Cnidus Philip of Opus Xenocrates Crantor Polemon Crates of Athens Middle Arcesilaus Lacydes Telecles Evander Hegesinus New Carneades Clitomachus Charmadas Philo of Larissa Middle Platonists Antiochus Philo of Alexandria Plutarch Albinus Alcinous Atticus Maximus of Tyre Numenius of Apamea Longinus Origen the Pagan Neoplatonists Ammonius Saccas Plotinus Disciples of Plotinus Amelius Porphyry Iamblichus Sopater Sosipatra Aedesius Dexippus Chrysanthius Julian Sallustius Maximus of Ephesus Eusebius of Myndus Antoninus Hypatia Plutarch of Athens Macrobius Asclepigenia Hierocles Syrianus Hermias Aedesia Proclus Ammonius Hermiae Asclepiodotus Marinus Zenodotus Hegias Isidore Damascius Simplicius Priscian Olympiodorus John Philoponus v t e Ancient Greek schools of philosophy Pre-Socratic Schools Atomism Eleatics Ionian Ephesian Milesian Pluralism Pythagoreanism Sophistic Philosophers Anaxagoras Anaximander Anaximenes Democritus Empedocles Heraclitus Leucippus Melissus Parmenides Protagoras Pythagoras Thales Zeno of Elea Socratic Schools Cynicism Cyrenaics Eretrian school Megarian school Peripateticism Platonism Philosophers Antisthenes Aristippus Aristotle Diogenes of Sinope Euclid of Megara Phaedo of Elis Plato Socrates Hellenistic Schools Epicureanism Neoplatonism Neopythagoreanism Pyrrhonism Stoicism Philosophers Apollonius of Tyana Augustine Epictetus Epicurus John Philoponus Lucretius Plotinus Proclus Pyrrho Sextus Empiricus Zeno of Citium v t e Ancient Greece Outline Timeline History Geography Periods Cycladic civilization Minoan civilization Mycenaean civilization Greek Dark Ages Archaic period Classical Greece Hellenistic Greece Roman Greece Geography Aegean Sea Aeolis Alexandria Antioch Cappadocia Crete Cyprus Doris Ephesus Epirus Hellespont Ionia Ionian Sea Macedonia Magna Graecia Miletus Peloponnesus Pergamon Pontus Taurica Ancient Greek colonies City states Politics Military City states Argos Athens Byzantion Chalcis Corinth Eretria Kerkyra Larissa Megalopolis Megara Rhodes Samos Sparta Syracuse Thebes Politics Boeotarch Boule Koinon Proxeny Strategos Tagus Tyrant Amphictyonic League Athenian Agora Areopagus Ecclesia Graphē paranómōn Heliaia Ostracism Spartan Apella Ephor Gerousia Harmost Macedon Synedrion Koinon Military Wars Athenian military Antigonid Macedonian army Army of Macedon Ballista Cretan archers Hellenistic armies Hippeis Hoplite Hetairoi Macedonian phalanx Phalanx Peltast Pezhetairos Sarissa Sacred Band of Thebes Sciritae Seleucid army Spartan army Toxotai Xiphos Xyston People List of ancient Greeks Rulers Kings of Argos Archons of Athens Kings of Athens Kings of Commagene Diadochi Kings of Lydia Kings of Macedonia Kings of Paionia Attalid kings of Pergamon Kings of Pontus Kings of Sparta Tyrants of Syracuse Philosophers Anaxagoras Anaximander Anaximenes Antisthenes Aristotle Democritus Diogenes of Sinope Empedocles Epicurus Gorgias Heraclitus Hypatia Leucippus Parmenides Plato Protagoras Pythagoras Socrates Thales Zeno Authors Aeschylus Aesop Alcaeus Archilochus Aristophanes Bacchylides Euripides Herodotus Hesiod Hipponax Homer Ibycus Lucian Menander Mimnermus Panyassis Philocles Pindar Plutarch Polybius Sappho Simonides Sophocles Stesichorus Theognis Thucydides Timocreon Tyrtaeus Xenophon Others Agesilaus II Agis II Alcibiades Alexander the Great Aratus Archimedes Aspasia Demosthenes Epaminondas Euclid Hipparchus Hippocrates Leonidas Lycurgus Lysander Milo of Croton Miltiades Pausanias Pericles Philip of Macedon Philopoemen Praxiteles Ptolemy Pyrrhus Solon Themistocles Groups Philosophers Playwrights Poets Tyrants By culture Ancient Greek tribes Thracian Greeks Ancient Macedonians Society Culture Society Agriculture Calendar Clothing Coinage Cuisine Economy Education Festivals Funeral and burial practices Homosexuality Law Olympic Games Pederasty Philosophy Prostitution Religion Slavery Warfare Wedding customs Wine Arts and science Architecture Greek Revival architecture Astronomy Literature Mathematics Medicine Music Musical system Pottery Sculpture Technology Theatre Religion Funeral and burial practices Mythology mythological figures Temple Twelve Olympians Underworld Sacred places Eleusis Delphi Delos Dodona Mount Olympus Olympia Structures Athenian Treasury Lion Gate Long Walls Philippeion Theatre of Dionysus Tunnel of Eupalinos Temples Aphaea Artemis Athena Nike Erechtheion Hephaestus Hera, Olympia Parthenon Samothrace Zeus, Olympia Language Proto-Greek Mycenaean Homeric Dialects Aeolic Arcadocypriot Attic Doric Ionic Locrian Macedonian Pamphylian Koine Writing Linear A Linear B Cypriot syllabary Greek alphabet Greek numerals Attic numerals Lists Cities in Epirus People Place names Stoae Temples Theatres Category Portal v t e Aristotelianism Overview Peripatetic school Physics Ethics Term logic Theology (unmoved mover) Ideas and interests Correspondence theory of truth Hexis Virtue ethics (golden mean) Four causes Telos Phronesis Eudaimonia Arete Temporal finitism Antiperistasis Philosophy of nature (sublunary sphere) Potentiality and actuality Universals (substantial form) Aristotle's biology Hylomorphism Mimesis Catharsis Substance (hypokeimenon, ousia, transcendentals) Essence–accident Category of being Minima naturalia Magnanimity Sensus communis Rational animal Genus–differentia Corpus Aristotelicum Physics Organon Nicomachean Ethics Politics Metaphysics On the Soul Rhetoric Poetics Followers Plato Alexander the Great Theophrastus Avicenna Averroes Maimonides Thomas Aquinas Alasdair MacIntyre Martha Nussbaum Related topics Platonism Commentaries on Aristotle Scholasticism Conimbricenses Pseudo-Aristotle Views on women Philosophy portal v t e Metaphysics Metaphysicians Parmenides Plato Aristotle Plotinus Duns Scotus Thomas Aquinas Francisco Suárez Nicolas Malebranche René Descartes John Locke David Hume Thomas Reid Immanuel Kant Isaac Newton Arthur Schopenhauer Baruch Spinoza Georg W. F. Hegel George Berkeley Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Henri Bergson Friedrich Nietzsche Charles Sanders Peirce Joseph Maréchal Ludwig Wittgenstein Martin Heidegger Alfred N. Whitehead Bertrand Russell Dorothy Emmet G. E. Moore Jean-Paul Sartre Gilbert Ryle Hilary Putnam P. F. Strawson R. G. Collingwood Adolph Stöhr Rudolf Carnap Saul Kripke Willard V. O. Quine G. E. M. Anscombe Donald Davidson Michael Dummett David Malet Armstrong David Lewis Alvin Plantinga Peter van Inwagen Derek Parfit more ... Theories Abstract object theory Action theory Anti-realism Determinism Dualism Enactivism Essentialism Existentialism Free will Idealism Libertarianism Liberty Materialism Meaning of life Monism Naturalism Nihilism Phenomenalism Realism Physicalism Pirsig's metaphysics of Quality Platonic idealism Relativism Scientific realism Solipsism Subjectivism Substance theory Type theory Concepts Abstract object Anima mundi Being Category of being Causality Choice Cogito ergo sum Concept Embodied cognition Entity Essence Existence Experience Hypostatic abstraction Idea Identity Identity and change Information Insight Intelligence Intention Linguistic modality Matter Meaning Memetics Mental representation Mind Motion Necessity Notion Object Pattern Perception Physical body Principle Property Qualia Quality Reality Soul Subject Substantial form Thought Time Truth Type–token distinction Universal Unobservable Value more ... Related topics Axiology Cosmology Epistemology Feminist metaphysics Interpretations of quantum mechanics Meta- Ontology Philosophy of mind Philosophy of psychology Philosophy of self Philosophy of space and time Teleology Theoretical physics Category Portal v t e Epistemology Epistemologists Thomas Aquinas Augustine of Hippo William Alston Robert Audi A. J. Ayer George Berkeley Laurence BonJour René Descartes John Dewey Fred Dretske Edmund Gettier Roger Gibson Alvin Goldman Nelson Goodman Paul Grice David Hume Immanuel Kant Søren Kierkegaard Saul Kripke David Lewis John Locke G. E. Moore Robert Nozick Alvin Plantinga Plato Hilary Putnam Thomas Reid Gilbert Ryle P. F. Strawson Willard Van Orman Quine Bertrand Russell Baruch Spinoza Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Nicholas Wolterstorff Vienna Circle Theories Coherentism Constructivist epistemology Contextualism Determinism Empiricism Evolutionary epistemology Fallibilism Feminist epistemology Fideism Foundationalism Genetic epistemology Holism Infinitism Innatism Internalism and externalism Naïve realism Naturalized epistemology Phenomenalism Positivism Reductionism Reliabilism Representative realism Rationalism Skepticism Theory of forms Transcendental idealism Uniformitarianism Concepts A priori knowledge Analysis Analytic–synthetic distinction Belief Causality Common sense Descriptive knowledge Exploratory thought Gettier problem Justification Knowledge Induction Objectivity Problem of induction Problem of other minds Perception Proposition Regress argument Simplicity Speculative reason Truth more... Related articles Outline of epistemology Alethiology Faith and rationality Formal epistemology Meta-epistemology Philosophy of perception Philosophy of science Social epistemology Portal Category Task Force Stubs Discussion v t e Social and political philosophy Philosophers Ambedkar Arendt Aristotle Augustine Aurobindo Aquinas Aron Averroes Azurmendi Badiou Bakunin Baudrillard Bauman Benoist Bentham Berlin Bonald Bosanquet Burke Judith Butler Camus Chanakya Chomsky Cicero Comte Confucius De Beauvoir Debord Du Bois Durkheim Emerson Engels Foucault Fourier Franklin Gandhi Gehlen Gentile Al-Ghazali Gramsci Grotius Habermas Han Fei Hayek Hegel Heidegger Hobbes Hume Irigaray Jefferson Kant Kierkegaard Kirk Kropotkin Laozi Le Bon Le Play Leibniz Lenin Locke Luxemburg Machiavelli Maistre Malebranche Mao Marcuse Maritain Marsilius Marx Mencius Michels Mill Mises Montesquieu Möser Mozi Muhammad Negri Niebuhr Nietzsche Nozick Oakeshott Ortega Paine Pareto Pettit Plamenatz Plato Polanyi Popper Radhakrishnan Rand Rawls Renan Rothbard Rousseau Royce Russell Sade Santayana Sarkar Sartre Schmitt Searle Shang Simonović Skinner Smith Socrates Sombart Spann Spencer Spinoza Spirito Stirner Strauss Sun Sun Tzu Taine Taylor Thucydides Thoreau Tocqueville Vivekananda Voltaire Walzer Weber Žižek Social theories Ambedkarism Anarchism Authoritarianism Collectivism Communism Communitarianism Conflict theories Confucianism Consensus theory Conservatism Contractualism Cosmopolitanism Culturalism Fascism Feminist political theory Gandhism Individualism Legalism Liberalism Libertarianism Mohism National liberalism Republicanism Social constructionism Social constructivism Social Darwinism Social determinism Socialism Utilitarianism Vaisheshika Social concepts Civil disobedience Democracy Four occupations Justice Law Mandate of Heaven Peace Property Revolution Rights Social contract Society War more... Related articles Jurisprudence Philosophy and economics Philosophy of education Philosophy of history Philosophy of love Philosophy of sex Philosophy of social science Political ethics Social epistemology Category Portal Task Force v t e Catholic virtue ethics Great Commandment; "On these two commandments hang all the law and the prophets." – Matthew 22:35-40 Cardinal virtues Prudence (Prudentia) Justice (Iustitia) Fortitude (Fortitudo) Temperance (Temperantia) Sources: Plato Republic, Book IV Cicero Ambrose Augustine of Hippo Thomas Aquinas Catechism of the Catholic Church, 1805–1809 Theological virtues Faith (Fides) Hope (Spes) Charity (Caritas) Sources: Paul the Apostle 1 Corinthians 13 Catechism of the Catholic Church, 1812–1829 Seven heavenly virtues Chastity (Castitas) Temperance (Temperantia) Charity (Caritas) Diligence (Industria) Patience (Patientia) Kindness (Humanitas) Humility (Humilitas) Source: Church Fathers Seven deadly sins Lust (Luxuria) Gluttony (Gula) Greed (Avaritia) Sloth (Acedia) Wrath (Ira) Envy (Invidia) Pride (Superbia) Source: Prudentius, Psychomachia People: Evagrius Ponticus John Cassian Pope Gregory I Dante Alighieri Peter Binsfeld Related concepts Ten Commandments Four last things Sin Christian views on sin Original sin Christian views on the Old Covenant Hamartiology (Latin names in bracketed italics) Catholic philosophy Catholic social teaching Catholicism portal Philosophy portal v t e Ethics Theories Casuistry Consequentialism Deontology Kantian ethics Ethics of care Existentialist ethics Meta-ethics Particularism Pragmatic ethics Role ethics Virtue ethics Concepts Autonomy Axiology Belief Conscience Consent Equality Care Free will Good and evil Happiness Ideal Justice Morality Norm Freedom Principles Suffering or Pain Stewardship Sympathy Trust Value Virtue Wrong full index... Philosophers Laozi Plato Aristotle Diogenes Valluvar Cicero Confucius Augustine of Hippo Mencius Mozi Xunzi Thomas Aquinas Baruch Spinoza David Hume Immanuel Kant Georg W. F. Hegel Arthur Schopenhauer Jeremy Bentham John Stuart Mill Søren Kierkegaard Henry Sidgwick Friedrich Nietzsche G. E. Moore Karl Barth Paul Tillich Dietrich Bonhoeffer Philippa Foot John Rawls John Dewey Bernard Williams J. L. Mackie G. E. M. Anscombe William Frankena Alasdair MacIntyre R. M. Hare Peter Singer Derek Parfit Thomas Nagel Robert Merrihew Adams Charles Taylor Joxe Azurmendi Christine Korsgaard Martha Nussbaum more... Applied ethics Bioethics Business ethics Discourse ethics Environmental ethics Legal ethics Media ethics Medical ethics Nursing ethics Professional ethics Sexual ethics Ethics of eating meat Ethics of technology Related articles Christian ethics Descriptive ethics Ethics in religion Evolutionary ethics Feminist ethics History of ethics Ideology Islamic ethics Jewish ethics Normative ethics Philosophy of law Political philosophy Social philosophy Portal Category v t e Philosophy of language Philosophers Plato (Cratylus) Gorgias Confucius Xunzi Aristotle Stoics Pyrrhonists Scholasticism Ibn Rushd Ibn Khaldun Thomas Hobbes Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Johann Herder Ludwig Noiré Wilhelm von Humboldt Fritz Mauthner Paul Ricœur Ferdinand de Saussure Gottlob Frege Franz Boas Paul Tillich Edward Sapir Leonard Bloomfield Zhuangzi Henri Bergson Lev Vygotsky Ludwig Wittgenstein Philosophical Investigations Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus Bertrand Russell Rudolf Carnap Jacques Derrida Of Grammatology Limited Inc Benjamin Lee Whorf Gustav Bergmann J. L. Austin Noam Chomsky Hans-Georg Gadamer Saul Kripke A. J. Ayer G. E. M. Anscombe Jaakko Hintikka Michael Dummett Donald Davidson Roger Gibson Paul Grice Gilbert Ryle P. F. Strawson Willard Van Orman Quine Hilary Putnam David Lewis John Searle Joxe Azurmendi Scott Soames Stephen Yablo John Hawthorne Stephen Neale Paul Watzlawick Theories Causal theory of reference Contrast theory of meaning Contrastivism Conventionalism Cratylism Deconstruction Descriptivist theory of names Direct reference theory Dramatism Expressivism Linguistic determinism Logical atomism Logical positivism Mediated reference theory Nominalism Non-cognitivism Phallogocentrism Quietism Relevance theory Semantic externalism Semantic holism Structuralism Supposition theory Symbiosism Theological noncognitivism Theory of descriptions Verification theory Concepts Ambiguity Linguistic relativity Meaning Language Truth-bearer Proposition Use–mention distinction Concept Categories Set Class Intension Logical form Metalanguage Mental representation Principle of compositionality Property Sign Sense and reference Speech act Symbol Entity Sentence Statement more... Related articles Analytic philosophy Philosophy of information Philosophical logic Linguistics Pragmatics Rhetoric Semantics Formal semantics Semiotics Category Task Force Discussion v t e Philosophy of science Concepts Analysis Analytic–synthetic distinction A priori and a posteriori Causality Commensurability Consilience Construct Creative synthesis Demarcation problem Empirical evidence Explanatory power Fact Falsifiability Feminist method Ignoramus et ignorabimus Inductive reasoning Intertheoretic reduction Inquiry Nature Objectivity Observation Paradigm Problem of induction Scientific law Scientific method Scientific revolution Scientific theory Testability Theory choice Theory-ladenness Underdetermination Unity of science Metatheory of science Coherentism Confirmation holism Constructive empiricism Constructive realism Constructivist epistemology Contextualism Conventionalism Deductive-nomological model Hypothetico-deductive model Inductionism Epistemological anarchism Evolutionism Fallibilism Foundationalism Instrumentalism Pragmatism Model-dependent realism Naturalism Physicalism Positivism / reductionism / determinism Rationalism / empiricism Received view / semantic view of theories Scientific realism / anti-realism Scientific essentialism Scientific formalism Scientific skepticism Scientism Structuralism Uniformitarianism Vitalism Philosophy of Physics thermal and statistical Motion Chemistry Biology Environment Geography Social science Technology Engineering Artificial intelligence Computer science Information Mind Psychiatry Psychology Perception Space and time Related topics Alchemy Criticism of science Epistemology Faith and rationality History and philosophy of science History of science History of evolutionary thought Logic Metaphysics Pseudoscience Relationship between religion and science Rhetoric of science Sociology of scientific knowledge Sociology of scientific ignorance Philosophers of science by era Ancient Plato Aristotle Stoicism Epicureans Medieval Averroes Avicenna Roger Bacon William of Ockham Hugh of Saint Victor Dominicus Gundissalinus Robert Kilwardby Early modern Francis Bacon Thomas Hobbes René Descartes Galileo Galilei Pierre Gassendi Isaac Newton David Hume Classical modern Immanuel Kant Friedrich Schelling William Whewell Auguste Comte John Stuart Mill Herbert Spencer Wilhelm Wundt Charles Sanders Peirce Wilhelm Windelband Henri Poincaré Pierre Duhem Rudolf Steiner Karl Pearson Late modern Alfred North Whitehead Bertrand Russell Albert Einstein Otto Neurath C. D. Broad Michael Polanyi Hans Reichenbach Rudolf Carnap Karl Popper Carl Gustav Hempel W. V. O. Quine Thomas Kuhn Imre Lakatos Paul Feyerabend Jürgen Habermas Ian Hacking Bas van Fraassen Larry Laudan Daniel Dennett Portal Category Authority control WorldCat Identities VIAF: 108159964 LCCN: n79139459 ISNI: 0000 0001 2096 469X GND: 118594893 SELIBR: 196943 SUDOC: 027076164 BNF: cb11920019p (data) BIBSYS: 90059026 ULAN: 500248317 MusicBrainz: f414935c-7ea7-45d7-b243-d7c0990158d8 NLA: 35425332 NDL: 00452937 NKC: jn19981001996 ICCU: IT\ICCU\CFIV\007350 BNE: XX1155787 IATH: w6715dwv Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Plato&oldid=819661065" Categories: 420s BC births340s BC deaths5th-century BC Greek people4th-century BC Greek people4th-century BC philosophers4th-century BC poetsAcademic philosophersAncient Athenian philosophersAncient Greek metaphilosophersAncient Greek political philosophersAncient Greek metaphysiciansAncient Greek epistemologistsAncient Greek ethicistsAncient Greek physicistsAncient Greek wrestlersAncient Greek slaves and freedmenAncient SyracuseAttic Greek writersGreek speculative fiction writersEpigrammatists of the Greek AnthologyOntologistsPhilosophers of educationPhilosophers of languagePhilosophers of lawPlatoPlatonismPupils of SocratesMoral realistsHidden categories: Articles with Encyclopædia Britannica linksAll articles that may contain original researchArticles that may contain original research from July 2017All articles with dead external linksArticles with dead external links from December 2017Articles with permanently dead external linksCS1 maint: BOT: original-url status unknownWikipedia indefinitely move-protected pagesWikipedia pages semi-protected against vandalismArticles with hCardsArticles containing Ancient Greek-language textArticles with specifically marked weasel-worded phrases from July 2017Wikipedia articles needing factual verification from July 2017Articles containing Greek-language textPages using div col without cols and colwidth parametersPages using Columns-list with deprecated parametersArticles containing Latin-language textWikipedia articles incorporating the template Lives of the Eminent PhilosophersArticles with Project Gutenberg linksArticles with Internet Archive linksArticles with LibriVox linksArticles incorporating a citation from the 1913 Catholic Encyclopedia with Wikisource referenceAC with 16 elementsWikipedia articles with VIAF identifiersWikipedia articles with LCCN identifiersWikipedia articles with ISNI identifiersWikipedia articles with GND identifiersWikipedia articles with SELIBR identifiersWikipedia articles with BNF identifiersWikipedia articles with BIBSYS identifiersWikipedia articles with ULAN identifiersWikipedia articles with MusicBrainz identifiersWikipedia articles with NLA identifiersWikipedia articles with SBN identifiersWikipedia articles with SNAC-ID identifiers


Navigation menu Personal tools Not logged inTalkContributionsCreate accountLog in Namespaces ArticleTalk Variants Views ReadView sourceView history More Search Navigation Main pageContentsFeatured contentCurrent eventsRandom articleDonate to WikipediaWikipedia store Interaction HelpAbout WikipediaCommunity portalRecent changesContact page Tools What links hereRelated changesUpload fileSpecial pagesPermanent linkPage informationWikidata itemCite this page Print/export Create a bookDownload as PDFPrintable version In other projects Wikimedia CommonsWikibooksWikiquoteWikisource Languages AfrikaansAlemannischአማርኛÆngliscالعربيةAragonésAsturianuAvañe'ẽAzərbaycancaتۆرکجهবাংলাBân-lâm-gúBasa BanyumasanБашҡортсаБеларускаяБеларуская (тарашкевіца)‎भोजपुरीБългарскиབོད་ཡིགBosanskiBrezhonegБуряадCatalàЧӑвашлаCebuanoČeštinaCorsuCymraegDanskDavvisámegiellaDeutschDolnoserbskiEestiΕλληνικάEmiliàn e rumagnòlEspañolEsperantoEstremeñuEuskaraفارسیFiji HindiFøroysktFrançaisFryskGaeilgeGàidhligGalego贛語ગુજરાતી𐌲𐌿𐍄𐌹𐍃𐌺गोंयची कोंकणी / Gõychi Konknni客家語/Hak-kâ-ngî한국어Հայերենहिन्दीHrvatskiIdoIgboIlokanoবিষ্ণুপ্রিয়া মণিপুরীBahasa IndonesiaInterlinguaInterlingueИронÍslenskaItalianoעבריתBasa Jawaಕನ್ನಡქართულიҚазақшаKiswahiliKreyòl ayisyenKurdîКыргызчаLadinoЛезгиລາວLatinaLatviešuLëtzebuergeschLietuviųLigureLimburgsLivvinkarjalaLa .lojban.LumbaartMagyarमैथिलीМакедонскиMalagasyമലയാളംमराठीმარგალურიمصرىمازِرونیBahasa MelayuBaso MinangkabauMìng-dĕ̤ng-ngṳ̄MirandésМонголမြန်မာဘာသာNāhuatlNederlandsNedersaksiesनेपाली日本語НохчийнNordfriiskNorskNorsk nynorskNovialOccitanOromooOʻzbekcha/ўзбекчаਪੰਜਾਬੀپنجابیPapiamentuپښتوPatoisភាសាខ្មែរPiemontèisTok PisinPlattdüütschPolskiPortuguêsQaraqalpaqshaRipoarischRomânăRuna SimiРусиньскыйРусскийСаха тылаसंस्कृतम्SarduScotsShqipSicilianuසිංහලSimple EnglishسنڌيSlovenčinaSlovenščinaСловѣньскъ / ⰔⰎⰑⰂⰡⰐⰠⰔⰍⰟکوردیСрпски / srpskiSrpskohrvatski / српскохрватскиSuomiSvenskaTagalogதமிழ்TaqbaylitТатарча/tatarçaతెలుగుไทยТоҷикӣᏣᎳᎩTürkçeTürkmençeУкраїнськаاردوئۇيغۇرچە / UyghurcheVènetoVepsän kel’Tiếng ViệtVolapükVõroWalon文言Winaray吴语ייִדישYorùbá粵語ZazakiZeêuwsŽemaitėška中文Kabɩyɛ Edit links This page was last edited on 10 January 2018, at 16:28. Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization. Privacy policy About Wikipedia Disclaimers Contact Wikipedia Developers Cookie statement Mobile view (window.RLQ=window.RLQ||[]).push(function(){mw.config.set({"wgPageParseReport":{"limitreport":{"cputime":"2.112","walltime":"2.437","ppvisitednodes":{"value":24526,"limit":1000000},"ppgeneratednodes":{"value":0,"limit":1500000},"postexpandincludesize":{"value":793999,"limit":2097152},"templateargumentsize":{"value":205501,"limit":2097152},"expansiondepth":{"value":16,"limit":40},"expensivefunctioncount":{"value":9,"limit":500},"entityaccesscount":{"value":1,"limit":400},"timingprofile":["100.00% 1888.364 1 -total"," 15.10% 285.140 1 Template:Reflist"," 13.09% 247.246 68 Template:Cite_book"," 12.22% 230.823 1 Template:Navboxes"," 8.75% 165.277 38 Template:Isbn"," 7.84% 147.990 4 Template:Lang"," 7.54% 142.408 1 Template:Infobox_philosopher"," 7.24% 136.800 1 Template:Infobox_person"," 6.75% 127.514 74 Template:Sfn"," 6.54% 123.510 24 Template:Navbox"]},"scribunto":{"limitreport-timeusage":{"value":"1.038","limit":"10.000"},"limitreport-memusage":{"value":25358285,"limit":52428800}},"cachereport":{"origin":"mw1322","timestamp":"20180116135318","ttl":1900800,"transientcontent":false}}});});(window.RLQ=window.RLQ||[]).push(function(){mw.config.set({"wgBackendResponseTime":2590,"wgHostname":"mw1322"});});


Plato - Photos and All Basic Informations

Plato More Links

This Article Is Semi-protected Due To VandalismPlato (disambiguation)Platon (disambiguation)SilanionClassical AthensApology (Plato)PhaedoSymposium (Plato)Republic (Plato)Ancient PhilosophyWestern PhilosophyList Of Schools Of PhilosophyPlatonismRhetoricArtLiteratureEpistemologyJusticeVirtuePoliticsEducationFamilyMilitarismFriendshipLovePlato's Tripartite Theory Of SoulHyperuranionMetaxyKhôraMethexisTheia ManiaAgathos Kai SophosPoiesisPhilotimonTemplate:PlatonismSocratesParmenidesPythagorasHeraclitusWestern PhilosophyCategory:PlatoRaphaelThe School Of AthensEarly Life Of PlatoCategory:Dialogues Of PlatoPlatonismPlatonic EpistemologyPlatonic IdealismPlatonic RealismDemiurgeTheory Of FormsTranscendentalsForm Of The GoodThird Man ArgumentEuthyphro DilemmaPlato's Five RegimesPhilosopher KingPlato's Unwritten DoctrinesPlato's Political PhilosophyAtlantisRing Of GygesAllegory Of The CaveAnalogy Of The Divided LineAnalogy Of The SunShip Of StateMyth Of ErChariot AllegoryCommentaries On PlatoPlatonic AcademySocratic ProblemMiddle PlatonismNeoplatonismNeoplatonism And ChristianityAllegorical Interpretations Of PlatoDefinist FallacyPortal:PhilosophyTemplate:PlatonismTemplate Talk:PlatonismHelp:IPA/EnglishAncient Greek LanguageHelp:IPA/GreekAttic GreekPhilosopherClassical GreecePlatonic AcademyAncient AthensWestern WorldPhilosophyWestern PhilosophyAncient Greek PhilosophySocratesAristotleWestern PhilosophyScienceAlfred North WhiteheadWestern ReligionSpiritualityDialogueDialecticPolitical PhilosophyPlato's RepublicPlato's LawsParmenidesHeraclitusPythagorasStanford Encyclopedia Of PhilosophyHistory Of PhilosophyEthicalPoliticalMetaphysicalEpistemologicalThomas AquinasImmanuel KantEarly Life Of PlatoAeginaAriston (Athenian)Diogenes LaertiusKing Of AthensCodrusMesseniaMelanthusPerictioneLegislatorLyric PoetrySolonCharmidesCritiasThirty TyrantsOligarchyRegimePeloponnesian WarAdeimantus Of CollytusGlauconPotoneSpeusippusThe Republic (Plato)Memorabilia (Xenophon)XenophonCratylusParmenidesEuclid Of MegaraDebra NailsSeventh Letter (Plato)Twelve OlympiansApolloPyrilampesAchaemenid EmpirePericlesParmenides (Plato)Charmides (dialogue)Protagoras (dialogue)Republic (Plato)Family TreeDiogenes LaërtiusWrestlingEnlargeVilla Of The PapyriDionysusPoseidonMiddle AgeApuleiusSpeusippusGymnasticsDicaearchusIsthmian GamesCratylusHeraclitusPre-Socratic PhilosophyAmbroseJeremiahAugustineThe City Of GodHebrewWikipedia:Manual Of Style/Words To WatchSeder HadorothHebrew CalendarWikipedia:VerifiabilityItalySicilyEgyptCyrene, LibyaAcademyStadion (unit Of Length)AcademusCastor And PolluxRegions Of Ancient GreeceLucius Cornelius SullaJustinian IByzantiumChristianitySyracuse, SicilyDionysius I Of SyracuseDion Of SyracuseMina (unit)Seventh Letter (Plato)Dionysius II Of SyracuseCalippus Of SyracuseThracianTertullianEnlargePythagoreanismPythagorasR. M. HareRepublic (Plato)ScienceMoralsSoul (spirit)Orphism (religion)CiceroNumenius Of ApameaHendrick Ter BrugghenVeliaMetaphysicsMythologyHeraclitusCratylusSkepticismParmenidesBeingOntologyTheologySocratic ProblemEnlargeSocratesLouvreApology (Plato)MeletusPhaedoSecond Letter (Plato)XenophonAristophanesTheory Of FormsHomerHesiodEnlargeThe School Of AthensRaphaelNicomachean EthicsTimaeus (dialogue)The FormsCritoKnowledgeAfterlifeRealityNatureMusesPhaedrus (Plato)Republic (Plato)Ion (dialogue)HomerIliadPlatonic RealismTheaetetus (dialogue)Allegory Of The CaveThe Divided Line Of PlatoPhilosopher KingTheory Of FormsPlatonic RealismProblem Of UniversalsArchetypeAbstractionType (metaphysics)Property (metaphysics)Greek LanguageUniversal (metaphysics)Platonic EpistemologyKnowledgeJustified True BeliefTheaetetus (dialogue)Edmund GettierCircular ReasoningMeno (Plato)Anamnesis (philosophy)Sophist (dialogue)Statesman (dialogue)Republic (dialogue)Parmenides (dialogue)DialecticTimaeus (dialogue)FoundationalismInfinite RegressionThe Republic (Plato)EnlargeOxyrhynchus PapyriState (polity)Laws (dialogue)Timaeus (dialogue)TorsoNavelAthenian DemocracyEnlargeFree WillReasonInterpersonal AttractionPhilosopher KingModerateWisdomCourageKnowledgeGoodness And Value TheoryExistenceAristocracyTimocracyOligarchyDemocracyTyrannySpartaPlato's Unwritten DoctrinesPhysics (Aristotle)Phaedrus (dialogue)LogosSeventh Letter (Plato)AristoxenusSimplicius Of CiliciaAlexander Of AphrodisiasMetaphysics (Aristotle)PlotinusFicinoHeinrich GomperzInternational Congress Of PhilosophyDialecticSimon BlackburnHegelKarl PopperStephanus PaginationEpistles (Plato)Henri EstienneStephanus PaginationEnlargeJean De SerresTetralogyTiberiusThrasyllus Of MendesApology (Plato)Charmides (dialogue)CritoEuthyphroGorgias (dialogue)Hippias MinorHippias MajorIon (dialogue)Laches (dialogue)Lysis (dialogue)Protagoras (dialogue)Cratylus (dialogue)Euthydemus (dialogue)MenoParmenides (dialogue)PhaedoPhaedrus (dialogue)Republic (dialogue)Symposium (Plato)Theaetetus (dialogue)Critias (dialogue)Sophist (dialogue)Statesman (dialogue)Timaeus (dialogue)PhilebusLaws (dialogue)First AlcibiadesSecond AlcibiadesClitophon (dialogue)EpinomisEpistles (Plato)Hipparchus (dialogue)Menexenus (dialogue)Minos (dialogue)Rival LoversTheagesAxiochus (dialogue)Definitions (Plato)Demodocus (dialogue)Epigrams (Plato)Eryxias (dialogue)Halcyon (dialogue)On JusticeOn VirtueSisyphus (dialogue)Lewis Campbell (classicist)StylometryAporiaApology (Plato)MenoGorgias (dialogue)Phaedrus (Plato)CritoEuthyphroLysis (dialogue)Charmides (dialogue)Republic (Plato)Protagoras (dialogue)EnlargeSymposium (Plato)Anselm FeuerbachSymposium (Plato)Theaetetus (dialogue)Euclid Of MegaraTrial Of SocratesApology (Plato)SophismOracle At DelphiTheaetetus (dialogue)EuthyphroMenoAnytusGorgiasRepublicCritoProtagorasCallias IIIHipponicusSymposium (Plato)Phaedrus (Plato)AristophanesCharmidesCritiasEuthyphro (prophet)Cratylus (dialogue)EuthyphroProdicusApology (Plato)DrachmaTheaetetus (dialogue)EnlargeProcess And RealityMiddle AgesScholasticismByzantine EmpireConstantinopleGeorge Gemistos PlethonCosimo De' MediciCouncil Of FerraraMarsilio FicinoIranClose ReadingAl-FarabiAvicennaAverroesHunayn Ibn IshaqRenaissanceScholasticismLorenzo De' MediciNiccolò MachiavelliThe PrinceMetempsychosisPolyamoryEuthanasiaBasilios BessarionFall Of ManPure MathematicsApplied MathematicsNumber TheoryArithmeticGottlob FregeKurt GödelAlonzo ChurchAlfred TarskiAlbert EinsteinOntologyMoralFriedrich NietzscheBeyond Good And EvilMartin HeideggerBeingBeing And TimeKarl PopperThe Open Society And Its EnemiesUtopiaThe Republic (Plato)TotalitarianismLeo StraussJewish PhilosophyIslamic PhilosophyPolitical PhilosophyMaimonidesAl-FarabiNeoplatonismEnlargeGreek MinusculeList Of Manuscripts Of Plato's DialoguesTextual CriticismThrasyllus Of MendesOxford UniversitySiglaArethas Of CaesareaPatriarchPhotios I Of ConstantinopleOxyrhynchus PapyriOxford Classical TextsNag Hammadi LibraryOlympiodorus The YoungerPlutarchProclusIamblichusEusebiusStobaeusFilippo ValoriFrancesco BerlinghieriMarsilio FicinoGeorge Gemistus PlethonHenri EstienneGenevaJean De SerresStephanus PaginationOxford Classical TextsJohn Burnet (classicist)E. R. DoddsHackett Publishing CompanyJohn McDowellPlato's Academy MosaicThe School Of AthensFrescoRaphaelPortal:PhilosophyCambridge PlatonistsList Of Speakers In Plato's DialoguesPlato's ProblemPlato's Unwritten DoctrinesPlatonic LovePlatonic SolidEllen Francis MasonAllegorical Interpretations Of PlatoHarold F. ChernissArchestratus Of PhrearrhiAncient Greek Personal NamesStoicismPhilologistApollodorus Of AthensThargelionApolloNeanthes Of CyzicusIsocratesAncient Olympic GamesPericlesSudaAeginaPeloponnesian WarSir Thomas BrowneRenaissancePlatonistUlrich Von Wilamowitz-MoellendorffArchonJonathan BarnesDebra NailsSeneca The YoungerFavorinusCleruchyPeace Of NiciasJohn Alexander Stewart (philosopher)Encyclopædia BritannicaMichel FoucaultJames Adam (classicist)Eduard ZellerCiceroDe DivinationeDavid SedleyInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0415073103JosiahHebrew CalendarSolomon’s TempleHebrew CalendarWikipedia:No Original ResearchRemahSeder HaDorothAnnicerisInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-415-07854-7PlotinusEnneadsHenologyFicinoKarl AlbertHans-Georg GadamerInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/1603849173International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/1472504852International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0271044810International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/080143792XBenjamin JowettInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/9401787743Wikipedia:Link RotCategory:CS1 Maint: BOT: Original-url Status UnknownInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/1603846123International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0819183563International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0199269718International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/9004091610Seneca The YoungerApuleiusAristophanesThe WaspsAristotleMetaphysics (Aristotle)CiceroDe DivinationeDiogenes LaërtiusLives Of The Eminent PhilosophersRobert Drew HicksWikisource:Charmides (Plato)Benjamin JowettWikisourceWikisource:GorgiasBenjamin JowettWikisourceWikisource:The RepublicBenjamin JowettWikisourcePlutarchWikisource:Lives (Dryden Translation)/PericlesJohn DrydenWikisourceSeneca The YoungerWikisource:Moral Letters To Lucilius/Letter 58WikisourceThucydidesWikisource:History Of The Peloponnesian WarRichard CrawleyWikisourceXenophonMemorabilia (Xenophon)International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-13-158591-6International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-471-54397-7JSTORDigital Object IdentifierInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-521-31101-2International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-521-64830-0International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-0-691-02072-3International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-7914-0433-1International Standard Serial NumberInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-87220-564-9International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/1-4051-1521-1International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/3-11-013912-XDigital Object IdentifierEncyclopædia BritannicaInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-90-04-04565-1John Robinson (historian)The American Scholar (magazine)Digital Object IdentifierInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-415-18984-5International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/9004123040International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-486-41605-4International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/960-382-664-2International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-90-420-3537-9International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0710036264International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-1-930972-04-9International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-8476-7662-5International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/1-4120-4843-5International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-8264-8408-5Bucknell UniversityInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-8387-5418-XHackett Publishing CompanyInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-87220-349-2International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-1-930972-02-5International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-671-69500-2Jacques DerridaInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/2-02-001958-2G. C. FieldInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-19-888040-5International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-19-875206-7International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-8264-9053-0W. K. C. GuthrieInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-521-31101-2W. K. C. GuthrieInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-521-31102-0International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-674-69906-8International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-691-09718-6Harvard University PressLoeb Classical LibraryGreek LanguageSocrates On Trial (play)International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-0-8020-9783-5International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-0-8020-9538-1International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-1-930972-71-1International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-19-508645-7International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-340-80385-1International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-521-80852-9International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-521-43610-9Suzanne LilarJulien GracqSuzanne LilarSuzanne LilarInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/1-4184-4977-6International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-1-930972-79-7International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-19-517510-7International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-1-930972-16-2International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-1-930972-01-8International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-1-930972-32-2International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-1-84760-047-9International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-521-48264-XOxford University PressOxford Classical TextsInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-1-930972-75-9John SallisInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-253-21071-2John SallisInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-253-21308-8International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-1-930972-09-4T. K. SeungInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-8476-8112-2International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-0-7546-6981-4International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-1-930972-29-2Thomas Taylor (neoplatonist)Gregory VlastosInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-691-10021-7Gregory VlastosInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-1-930972-13-1International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/978-0-226-99335-5WikisourceWikisourcePerseus ProjectProject GutenbergInternet ArchiveLibriVoxLoeb Classical LibraryIndiana Philosophy Ontology ProjectPhilPapersCatholic EncyclopediaTemplate:Plato NavboxTemplate Talk:Plato NavboxEarly Life Of PlatoPlatonismPlatonic EpistemologyPlatonic IdealismPlatonic RealismPlatonic LoveNeoplatonism And GnosticismPlatonism In The RenaissanceDemiurgeTheory Of FormsTranscendentalsForm Of The GoodThird Man ArgumentEuthyphro DilemmaPlato's Five RegimesPhilosopher KingPlato's Unwritten DoctrinesCultural Influence Of Plato's RepublicApology (Plato)Charmides (dialogue)Cratylus (dialogue)Critias (dialogue)CritoEuthydemus (dialogue)EuthyphroFirst AlcibiadesGorgias (dialogue)Hippias MajorHippias MinorIon (dialogue)Laches (dialogue)Papyrus Oxyrhynchus 228Laws (dialogue)Papyrus Oxyrhynchus 23Lysis (dialogue)Menexenus (dialogue)MenoParmenides (dialogue)PhaedoPapyrus Oxyrhynchus 229Phaedrus (dialogue)PhilebusProtagoras (dialogue)Republic (Plato)Sophist (dialogue)Statesman (dialogue)Symposium (Plato)Theaetetus (dialogue)Timaeus (dialogue)Axiochus (dialogue)Clitophon (dialogue)Definitions (Plato)Demodocus (dialogue)Epigrams (Plato)EpinomisEpistles (Plato)First Letter (Plato)Second Letter (Plato)Fifth Letter (Plato)Seventh LetterNinth Letter (Plato)Tenth Letter (Plato)Twelfth LetterEryxias (dialogue)Halcyon (dialogue)Hipparchus (dialogue)Minos (dialogue)On JusticeOn VirtueRival LoversSecond AlcibiadesSisyphus (dialogue)TheagesAtlantisRing Of GygesAllegory Of The CaveAnalogy Of The Divided LineAnalogy Of The SunShip Of StateMyth Of ErChariot AllegoryAllegorical Interpretations Of PlatoCommentaries On PlatoPlatonic AcademySocratic ProblemMiddle PlatonismNeoplatonismNeoplatonism And ChristianityPoitier Meets PlatoList Of Speakers In Plato's DialoguesPlato's DreamAriston Of AthensPyrilampesPerictioneAdeimantus Of CollytusGlauconPotoneSpeusippusTemplate:PlatonistsTemplate Talk:PlatonistsPlatonismPlatonic AcademySpeusippusHeraclides PonticusMenedemus Of PyrrhaEudoxus Of CnidusPhilip Of OpusXenocratesCrantorPolemon (scholarch)Crates Of AthensArcesilausLacydes Of CyreneTeleclesEvander (philosopher)Hegesinus Of PergamonCarneadesClitomachus (philosopher)CharmadasPhilo Of LarissaMiddle PlatonismAntiochus Of AscalonPhiloPlutarchAlbinus (philosopher)Alcinous (philosopher)Atticus (philosopher)Maximus Of TyreNumenius Of ApameaCassius Longinus (philosopher)Origen The PaganNeoplatonismAmmonius SaccasPlotinusDisciples Of PlotinusAmeliusPorphyry (philosopher)IamblichusSopater Of ApameaSosipatraAedesiusDexippus (philosopher)ChrysanthiusJulian (emperor)SallustiusMaximus Of EphesusEusebius Of MyndusAntoninus (philosopher)HypatiaPlutarch Of AthensMacrobiusAsclepigeniaHierocles Of AlexandriaSyrianusHermias (philosopher)AedesiaProclusAmmonius HermiaeAsclepiodotus Of AlexandriaMarinus Of NeapolisZenodotus (philosopher)HegiasIsidore Of AlexandriaDamasciusSimplicius Of CiliciaPriscian Of LydiaOlympiodorus The YoungerJohn PhiloponusTemplate:Ancient Greek Schools Of PhilosophyTemplate Talk:Ancient Greek Schools Of PhilosophyAncient Greek PhilosophyPre-Socratic PhilosophyAtomismEleaticsIonian School (philosophy)Ephesian SchoolMilesian SchoolPluralist SchoolPythagoreanismSophistAnaxagorasAnaximanderAnaximenes Of MiletusDemocritusEmpedoclesHeraclitusLeucippusMelissus Of SamosParmenidesProtagorasPythagorasThalesZeno Of EleaSocratesCynicism (philosophy)CyrenaicsEretrian SchoolMegarian SchoolPeripatetic SchoolPlatonismAntisthenesAristippusAristotleDiogenesEuclid Of MegaraPhaedo Of ElisSocratesHellenistic PhilosophyEpicureanismNeoplatonismNeopythagoreanismPyrrhonismStoicismApollonius Of TyanaAugustineEpictetusEpicurusJohn PhiloponusLucretiusPlotinusProclusPyrrhoSextus EmpiricusZeno Of CitiumTemplate:Ancient Greece TopicsTemplate Talk:Ancient Greece TopicsAncient GreeceOutline Of Ancient GreeceTimeline Of Ancient GreeceAncient GreeceRegions Of Ancient GreeceCycladic CultureMinoan CivilizationMycenaean GreeceGreek Dark AgesArchaic GreeceClassical GreeceHellenistic GreeceRoman GreeceRegions Of Ancient GreeceAegean SeaAeolisAlexandriaAntiochCappadociaCreteCyprusDoric HexapolisEphesusEpirus (ancient State)DardanellesIoniaIonian SeaMacedonia (ancient Kingdom)Magna GraeciaMiletusPeloponnesePergamonPontus (region)CrimeaColonies In AntiquityPolisAncient GreeceAncient Greek WarfarePolisArgosClassical AthensByzantiumChalcisAncient CorinthEretriaKerkyraLarissaMegalopolis, GreeceMegaraRhodesSamosSpartaSyracuse, SicilyThebes, GreeceAncient GreeceBoeotarchBoule (ancient Greece)KoinonProxenyStrategosTagus (title)TyrantAmphictyonic LeagueAthenian DemocracyAgoraAreopagusEcclesia (ancient Athens)Graphe ParanomonHeliaiaOstracismSpartan ConstitutionApellaEphorGerousiaHarmostMacedonia (ancient Kingdom)SynedrionKoinon Of MacedoniansAncient Greek WarfareList Of Wars Involving GreeceAthenian MilitaryAntigonid Macedonian ArmyAncient Macedonian ArmyBallistaCretan ArchersHellenistic ArmiesHippeisHopliteCompanion CavalryMacedonian PhalanxPhalanxPeltastPezhetairosSarissaSacred Band Of ThebesSciritaeSeleucid ArmySpartan ArmyToxotaiXiphosXystonCategory:Ancient GreeksList Of Ancient GreeksLists Of Rulers Of GreeceList Of Kings Of ArgosEponymous ArchonList Of Kings Of AthensList Of Rulers Of CommageneDiadochiList Of Kings Of LydiaList Of Kings Of MacedoniaList Of Rulers Of Thrace And DaciaAttalid DynastyList Of Kings Of PontusList Of Kings Of SpartaList Of Tyrants Of SyracuseAncient Greek PhilosophyAnaxagorasAnaximanderAnaximenes Of MiletusAntisthenesAristotleDemocritusDiogenes Of SinopeEmpedoclesEpicurusGorgiasHeraclitusHypatiaLeucippusParmenidesProtagorasPythagorasSocratesThalesZeno Of CitiumAncient Greek LiteratureAeschylusAesopAlcaeus Of MytileneArchilochusAristophanesBacchylidesEuripidesHerodotusHesiodHipponaxHomerIbycusLucianMenanderMimnermusPanyassisPhiloclesPindarPlutarchPolybiusSapphoSimonides Of CeosSophoclesStesichorusTheognis Of MegaraThucydidesTimocreonTyrtaeusXenophonAgesilaus IIAgis IIAlcibiadesAlexander The GreatAratus Of SicyonArchimedesAspasiaDemosthenesEpaminondasEuclidHipparchusHippocratesLeonidas ILycurgus Of SpartaLysanderMilo Of CrotonMiltiadesPausanias (general)PericlesPhilip II Of MacedonPhilopoemenPraxitelesPtolemyPyrrhus Of EpirusSolonThemistoclesList Of Ancient Greek PhilosophersList Of Ancient Greek PlaywrightsList Of Ancient Greek PoetsList Of Ancient Greek TyrantsList Of Ancient Greek TribesList Of Thracian GreeksList Of Ancient MacedoniansAncient GreeceAncient GreeceAncient GreeceAgriculture In Ancient GreeceHellenic CalendarsClothing In Ancient GreeceAncient Greek CoinageAncient Greek CuisineEconomy Of Ancient GreecePaideiaAthenian FestivalsAncient Greek Funeral And Burial PracticesHomosexuality In Ancient GreeceAncient Greek LawAncient Olympic GamesPederasty In Ancient GreeceAncient Greek PhilosophyProstitution In Ancient GreeceAncient Greek ReligionSlavery In Ancient GreeceAncient Greek WarfareAncient Greek Wedding CustomsAncient Greece And WineAncient Greek ArtAncient Greek ArchitectureGreek Revival ArchitectureAncient Greek AstronomyAncient Greek LiteratureGreek MathematicsAncient Greek MedicineMusic Of Ancient GreeceMusical System Of Ancient GreecePottery Of Ancient GreeceAncient Greek SculptureAncient Greek TechnologyTheatre Of Ancient GreeceAncient Greek ReligionAncient Greek Funeral And Burial PracticesGreek MythologyList Of Greek Mythological FiguresAncient Greek TempleTwelve OlympiansGreek UnderworldEleusisDelphiDelosDodonaMount OlympusOlympia, GreeceAthenian TreasuryLion GateLong WallsPhilippeionTheatre Of DionysusTunnel Of EupalinosAncient Greek TempleTemple Of AphaeaTemple Of ArtemisTemple Of Athena NikeErechtheionTemple Of HephaestusTemple Of Hera, OlympiaParthenonSamothrace Temple ComplexTemple Of Zeus, OlympiaAncient GreekProto-Greek LanguageMycenaean GreekHomeric GreekAncient Greek DialectsAeolic GreekArcadocypriot GreekAttic GreekDoric GreekIonic GreekLocrian GreekAncient Macedonian LanguagePamphylian GreekKoine GreekHistory Of The Greek AlphabetLinear ALinear BCypriot SyllabaryGreek AlphabetGreek NumeralsAttic NumeralsList Of Ancient Greek CitiesList Of Cities In Ancient EpirusList Of Ancient GreeksList Of Greek Place NamesList Of StoaeList Of Ancient Greek TemplesList Of Ancient Greek TheatresCategory:Ancient GreecePortal:Ancient GreeceTemplate:AristotelianismTemplate Talk:AristotelianismAristotelianismPeripatetic SchoolAristotelian PhysicsAristotelian EthicsTerm LogicAristotelian TheologyUnmoved MoverCorrespondence Theory Of TruthHexisVirtue EthicsGolden Mean (philosophy)Four CausesTelos (philosophy)PhronesisEudaimoniaArete (moral Virtue)Temporal FinitismAntiperistasisNature (philosophy)Sublunary SpherePotentiality And ActualityAristotle's Theory Of UniversalsSubstantial FormAristotle's BiologyHylomorphismMimesisCatharsisSubstance TheoryHypokeimenonOusiaTranscendentalsEssenceAccident (philosophy)Category Of BeingMinima NaturaliaMagnanimityCommon SenseRational AnimalGenus–differentia DefinitionCorpus AristotelicumPhysics (Aristotle)OrganonNicomachean EthicsPolitics (Aristotle)Metaphysics (Aristotle)On The SoulRhetoric (Aristotle)Poetics (Aristotle)Alexander The GreatTheophrastusAvicennaAverroesMaimonidesThomas AquinasAlasdair MacIntyreMartha NussbaumPlatonismCommentaries On AristotleScholasticismConimbricensesPseudo-AristotleAristotle's Views On WomenPortal:PhilosophyTemplate:MetaphysicsTemplate Talk:MetaphysicsMetaphysicsParmenidesAristotlePlotinusDuns ScotusThomas AquinasFrancisco SuárezNicolas MalebrancheRené DescartesJohn LockeDavid HumeThomas ReidImmanuel KantIsaac NewtonArthur SchopenhauerBaruch SpinozaGeorg Wilhelm Friedrich HegelGeorge BerkeleyGottfried Wilhelm LeibnizHenri BergsonFriedrich NietzscheCharles Sanders PeirceJoseph MaréchalLudwig WittgensteinMartin HeideggerAlfred North WhiteheadBertrand RussellDorothy EmmetG. E. MooreJean-Paul SartreGilbert RyleHilary PutnamP. F. StrawsonR. G. CollingwoodAdolph StöhrRudolf CarnapSaul KripkeWillard Van Orman QuineG. E. M. AnscombeDonald Davidson (philosopher)Michael DummettDavid Malet ArmstrongDavid Lewis (philosopher)Alvin PlantingaPeter Van InwagenDerek ParfitList Of MetaphysiciansAbstract Object TheoryAction Theory (philosophy)Anti-realismDeterminismMind-body DualismEnactivism (psychology)EssentialismExistentialismFree WillIdealismLibertarianism (metaphysics)LibertyMaterialismMeaning Of LifeMonismNaturalism (philosophy)NihilismPhenomenalismPhilosophical RealismPhysicalismPirsig's Metaphysics Of QualityPlatonic IdealismRelativismScientific RealismSolipsismSubjectivismSubstance TheoryType TheoryAbstract And ConcreteAnima MundiBeingCategory Of BeingCausalityChoiceCogito Ergo SumConceptEmbodied CognitionEntityEssenceExistenceExperienceHypostatic AbstractionIdeaIdentity (philosophy)Identity And ChangeInformationInsightIntelligenceIntentionLinguistic ModalityMatter (philosophy)Meaning (existential)MemeticsMental RepresentationMindMotion (physics)Metaphysical NecessityNotion (philosophy)Object (philosophy)PatternPerceptionPhysical BodyPrincipleProperty (philosophy)QualiaQuality (philosophy)RealitySoulSubject (philosophy)Substantial FormThoughtTimeTruthType–token DistinctionUniversal (metaphysics)UnobservableValue (ethics)Index Of Metaphysics ArticlesAxiologyCosmology (philosophy)EpistemologyFeminist MetaphysicsInterpretations Of Quantum MechanicsMetaOntologyPhilosophy Of MindPhilosophy Of PsychologyPhilosophy Of SelfPhilosophy Of Space And TimeTeleologyTheoretical PhysicsCategory:MetaphysicsPortal:MetaphysicsTemplate:EpistemologyTemplate Talk:EpistemologyEpistemologyList Of EpistemologistsThomas AquinasAugustine Of HippoWilliam AlstonRobert AudiA. J. AyerGeorge BerkeleyLaurence BonJourRené DescartesJohn DeweyFred DretskeEdmund GettierRoger GibsonAlvin GoldmanNelson GoodmanPaul GriceDavid HumeImmanuel KantSøren KierkegaardSaul KripkeDavid Lewis (philosopher)John LockeG. E. MooreRobert NozickAlvin PlantingaHilary PutnamThomas ReidGilbert RyleP. F. StrawsonWillard Van Orman QuineBertrand RussellBaruch SpinozaTimothy WilliamsonLudwig WittgensteinNicholas WolterstorffVienna CircleCategory:Epistemological TheoriesCoherentismConstructivist EpistemologyContextualismDeterminismEmpiricismEvolutionary EpistemologyFallibilismFeminist EpistemologyFideismFoundationalismGenetic EpistemologyHolismInfinitismInnatismInternalism And ExternalismNaïve RealismNaturalized EpistemologyPhenomenalismPositivismReductionismReliabilismDirect And Indirect RealismRationalismPhilosophical SkepticismTheory Of FormsTranscendental IdealismUniformitarianismCategory:Concepts In EpistemologyA Priori And A PosterioriPhilosophical AnalysisAnalytic–synthetic DistinctionBeliefCausalityCommon SenseDescriptive KnowledgeExploratory ThoughtGettier ProblemTheory Of JustificationKnowledgeInductive ReasoningObjectivity (philosophy)Problem Of InductionProblem Of Other MindsPerceptionPropositionRegress ArgumentSimplicitySpeculative ReasonTruthIndex Of Epistemology ArticlesOutline Of EpistemologyAlethiologyFaith And RationalityFormal EpistemologyMeta-epistemologyPhilosophy Of PerceptionPhilosophy Of ScienceSocial EpistemologyPortal:EpistemologyCategory:EpistemologyWikipedia:WikiProject Philosophy/EpistemologyCategory:Philosophy StubsWikipedia Talk:WikiProject PhilosophyTemplate:Social And Political PhilosophyTemplate Talk:Social And Political PhilosophySocial PhilosophyPolitical PhilosophyList Of Social And Political PhilosophersB. R. AmbedkarHannah ArendtAristotleAugustine Of HippoSri AurobindoThomas AquinasRaymond AronAverroesJoxe AzurmendiAlain BadiouMikhail BakuninJean BaudrillardZygmunt BaumanAlain De BenoistJeremy BenthamIsaiah BerlinLouis Gabriel Ambroise De BonaldBernard Bosanquet (philosopher)Edmund BurkeJudith ButlerAlbert CamusChanakyaNoam ChomskyCiceroAuguste ComteConfuciusSimone De BeauvoirGuy DebordW. E. B. Du BoisÉmile DurkheimRalph Waldo EmersonFriedrich EngelsMichel FoucaultCharles FourierBenjamin FranklinMahatma GandhiArnold GehlenGiovanni GentileAl-GhazaliAntonio GramsciHugo GrotiusJürgen HabermasHan FeiFriedrich HayekGeorg Wilhelm Friedrich HegelMartin HeideggerThomas HobbesDavid HumeLuce IrigarayThomas JeffersonImmanuel KantSøren KierkegaardRussell KirkPeter KropotkinLaoziGustave Le BonPierre Guillaume Frédéric Le PlayGottfried Wilhelm LeibnizVladimir LeninJohn LockeRosa LuxemburgNiccolò MachiavelliJoseph De MaistreNicolas MalebrancheMao ZedongHerbert MarcuseJacques MaritainMarsilius Of PaduaKarl MarxMenciusRobert MichelsJohn Stuart MillLudwig Von MisesMontesquieuJustus MöserMoziMuhammadAntonio NegriReinhold NiebuhrFriedrich NietzscheRobert NozickMichael OakeshottJosé Ortega Y GassetThomas PaineVilfredo ParetoPhilip PettitJohn PlamenatzKarl PolanyiKarl PopperSarvepalli RadhakrishnanAyn RandJohn RawlsErnest RenanMurray RothbardJean-Jacques RousseauJosiah RoyceBertrand RussellMarquis De SadeGeorge SantayanaPrabhat Ranjan SarkarJean-Paul SartreCarl SchmittJohn SearleShang YangLjubodrag SimonovićB. F. SkinnerAdam SmithSocratesWerner SombartOthmar SpannHerbert SpencerBaruch SpinozaUgo SpiritoMax StirnerLeo StraussSun Yat-senSun TzuHippolyte TaineCharles Taylor (philosopher)ThucydidesHenry David ThoreauAlexis De TocquevilleSwami VivekanandaVoltaireMichael WalzerMax WeberSlavoj ŽižekCategory:Social TheoriesAmbedkarismAnarchismAuthoritarianismCollectivismCommunismCommunitarianismConflict TheoriesConfucianismConsensus TheoryConservatismContractualismCosmopolitanismCulturalismFascismFeminist Political TheoryGandhismIndividualismLegalism (Chinese Philosophy)LiberalismLibertarianismMohismNational LiberalismRepublicanismSocial ConstructionismSocial ConstructivismSocial DarwinismSocial DeterminismSocialismUtilitarianismVaisheshikaCivil DisobedienceDemocracyFour OccupationsJusticeLawMandate Of HeavenPeacePropertyRevolutionRightsSocial ContractSocietyWarIndex Of Social And Political Philosophy ArticlesJurisprudencePhilosophy And EconomicsPhilosophy Of EducationPhilosophy Of HistoryPhilosophy Of LovePhilosophy Of SexPhilosophy Of Social SciencePolitical EthicsSocial EpistemologyCategory:Social PhilosophyPortal:Social And Political PhilosophyWikipedia:WikiProject Philosophy/Social And PoliticalTemplate:Catholic Virtue EthicsTemplate Talk:Catholic Virtue EthicsCatholic Virtue EthicsGreat CommandmentCardinal VirtuesPrudenceJustice (virtue)Fortitude (virtue)Temperance (virtue)Republic (Plato)CiceroAmbroseAugustine Of HippoThomas AquinasCatechism Of The Catholic ChurchFaith, Hope And Love, As Portrayed By Mary Lizzie Macomber (1861–1916)Theological VirtuesFaithHope (virtue)Charity (virtue)Paul The Apostle1 Corinthians 13Catechism Of The Catholic ChurchSeven VirtuesChastityTemperance (virtue)Charity (virtue)DiligencePatienceKindnessHumilityChurch FathersSeven Deadly SinsLustGluttonyGreedSloth (deadly Sin)AngerEnvyPridePrudentiusPsychomachiaEvagrius PonticusJohn CassianPope Gregory IDante AlighieriPeter BinsfeldTen Commandments In Catholic TheologyFour Last ThingsSinChristian Views On SinOriginal SinChristian Views On The Old CovenantHamartiologyLatinCatholic PhilosophyCatholic Social TeachingPortal:CatholicismPortal:PhilosophyTemplate:EthicsTemplate Talk:EthicsEthicsCasuistryConsequentialismDeontological EthicsKantian EthicsEthics Of CareExistentialismMeta-ethicsMoral ParticularismPragmatic EthicsRole EthicsVirtue EthicsAutonomyAxiologyBeliefConscienceConsentEgalitarianismEthics Of CareFree WillGood And EvilHappinessIdeal (ethics)JusticeMoralityNorm (philosophy)Political FreedomPrincipleSufferingStewardshipSympathyTrust (emotion)Value (ethics)VirtueWrongdoingIndex Of Ethics ArticlesLaoziAristotleDiogenesValluvarCiceroConfuciusAugustine Of HippoMenciusMoziXun KuangThomas AquinasBaruch SpinozaDavid HumeImmanuel KantGeorg Wilhelm Friedrich HegelArthur SchopenhauerJeremy BenthamJohn Stuart MillSøren KierkegaardHenry SidgwickFriedrich NietzscheG. E. MooreKarl BarthPaul TillichDietrich BonhoefferPhilippa FootJohn RawlsJohn DeweyBernard WilliamsJ. L. MackieG. E. M. AnscombeWilliam FrankenaAlasdair MacIntyreR. M. HarePeter SingerDerek ParfitThomas NagelRobert Merrihew AdamsCharles Taylor (philosopher)Joxe AzurmendiChristine KorsgaardMartha NussbaumList Of EthicistsApplied EthicsBioethicsBusiness EthicsDiscourse EthicsEnvironmental EthicsLegal EthicsMedia EthicsMedical EthicsNursing EthicsProfessional EthicsSexual EthicsEthics Of Eating MeatEthics Of TechnologyChristian EthicsDescriptive EthicsEthics In ReligionEvolutionary EthicsFeminist EthicsHistory Of EthicsIdeologyIslamic EthicsJewish EthicsNormative EthicsPhilosophy Of LawPolitical PhilosophySocial PhilosophyPortal:EthicsCategory:EthicsTemplate:Philosophy Of LanguageTemplate Talk:Philosophy Of LanguagePhilosophy Of LanguageList Of Philosophers Of LanguageCratylus (dialogue)GorgiasConfuciusXun KuangAristotleStoicismPyrrhonismScholasticismAverroesIbn KhaldunThomas HobbesGottfried Wilhelm LeibnizJohann Gottfried HerderLudwig NoiréWilhelm Von HumboldtFritz MauthnerPaul RicœurFerdinand De SaussureGottlob FregeFranz BoasPaul TillichEdward SapirLeonard BloomfieldZhuang ZhouHenri BergsonLev VygotskyLudwig WittgensteinPhilosophical InvestigationsTractatus Logico-PhilosophicusBertrand RussellRudolf CarnapJacques DerridaOf GrammatologyLimited IncBenjamin Lee WhorfGustav BergmannJ. L. AustinNoam ChomskyHans-Georg GadamerSaul KripkeA. J. AyerG. E. M. AnscombeJaakko HintikkaMichael DummettDonald Davidson (philosopher)Roger GibsonPaul GriceGilbert RyleP. F. StrawsonWillard Van Orman QuineHilary PutnamDavid Lewis (philosopher)John SearleJoxe AzurmendiScott SoamesStephen YabloJohn HawthorneStephen NealePaul WatzlawickCategory:Theories Of LanguageCausal Theory Of ReferenceContrastivismContrastivismConventionalismCratylismDeconstructionDescriptivist Theory Of NamesDirect Reference TheoryDramatismExpressivismLinguistic DeterminismLogical AtomismLogical PositivismMediated Reference TheoryNominalismNon-cognitivismPhallogocentrismQuietism (philosophy)Relevance TheorySemantic ExternalismSemantic HolismStructuralismSupposition TheorySymbiosismTheological NoncognitivismTheory Of DescriptionsVerificationismAmbiguityLinguistic RelativityMeaning (linguistics)LanguageTruth-bearerPropositionUse–mention DistinctionConceptCategorizationSet (mathematics)Class (philosophy)IntensionLogical FormMetalanguageMental RepresentationPrinciple Of CompositionalityProperty (philosophy)Sign (semiotics)Sense And ReferenceSpeech ActSymbolEntitySentence (linguistics)Statement (logic)Index Of Philosophy Of Language ArticlesAnalytic PhilosophyPhilosophy Of InformationPhilosophical LogicLinguisticsPragmaticsRhetoricSemanticsFormal Semantics (linguistics)SemioticsCategory:Philosophy Of LanguageWikipedia:WikiProject Philosophy/LanguageWikipedia Talk:WikiProject PhilosophyTemplate:Philosophy Of ScienceTemplate Talk:Philosophy Of SciencePhilosophy Of SciencePhilosophical AnalysisAnalytic–synthetic DistinctionA Priori And A PosterioriCausalityCommensurability (philosophy Of Science)ConsilienceConstruct (philosophy)Creative SynthesisDemarcation ProblemEmpirical EvidenceExplanatory PowerFactFalsifiabilityFeminist MethodIgnoramus Et IgnorabimusInductive ReasoningIntertheoretic ReductionInquiryNature (philosophy)Objectivity (philosophy)ObservationParadigmProblem Of InductionScientific LawScientific MethodScientific RevolutionScientific TheoryTestabilityTheory ChoiceTheory-ladennessUnderdeterminationUnity Of ScienceCategory:Metatheory Of ScienceCoherentismConfirmation HolismConstructive EmpiricismConstructive RealismConstructivist EpistemologyContextualismConventionalismDeductive-nomological ModelHypothetico-deductive ModelInductionismEpistemological AnarchismEvolutionismFallibilismFoundationalismInstrumentalismPragmatismModel-dependent RealismNaturalism (philosophy)PhysicalismPositivismReductionismDeterminismRationalismEmpiricismReceived View Of TheoriesSemantic View Of TheoriesScientific RealismAnti-realismScientific EssentialismScientific FormalismScientific SkepticismScientismStructuralism (philosophy Of Science)UniformitarianismVitalismPhilosophy Of PhysicsPhilosophy Of Thermal And Statistical PhysicsPhilosophy Of MotionPhilosophy Of ChemistryPhilosophy Of BiologyPhilosophy Of EnvironmentPhilosophy Of GeographyPhilosophy Of Social SciencePhilosophy Of TechnologyPhilosophy Of EngineeringPhilosophy Of Artificial IntelligencePhilosophy Of Computer SciencePhilosophy Of InformationPhilosophy Of MindPhilosophy Of PsychiatryPhilosophy Of PsychologyPhilosophy Of PerceptionPhilosophy Of Space And TimeIndex Of Philosophy Of Science ArticlesAlchemyCriticism Of ScienceEpistemologyFaith And RationalityHistory And Philosophy Of ScienceHistory Of ScienceHistory Of Evolutionary ThoughtLogicMetaphysicsPseudoscienceRelationship Between Religion And ScienceRhetoric Of ScienceSociology Of Scientific KnowledgeSociology Of Scientific IgnoranceList Of Philosophers Of ScienceAristotleStoicismEpicureanismAverroesAvicennaRoger BaconWilliam Of OckhamHugh Of Saint VictorDominicus GundissalinusRobert KilwardbyFrancis BaconThomas HobbesRené DescartesGalileo GalileiPierre GassendiIsaac NewtonDavid HumeImmanuel KantFriedrich Wilhelm Joseph SchellingWilliam WhewellAuguste ComteJohn Stuart MillHerbert SpencerWilhelm WundtCharles Sanders PeirceWilhelm WindelbandHenri PoincaréPierre DuhemRudolf SteinerKarl PearsonAlfred North WhiteheadBertrand RussellAlbert EinsteinOtto NeurathC. D. BroadMichael PolanyiHans ReichenbachRudolf CarnapKarl PopperCarl Gustav HempelWillard Van Orman QuineThomas KuhnImre LakatosPaul FeyerabendJürgen HabermasIan HackingBas Van FraassenLarry LaudanDaniel DennettPortal:Philosophy Of ScienceCategory:Philosophy Of ScienceHelp:Authority ControlVirtual International Authority FileLibrary Of Congress Control NumberInternational Standard Name IdentifierIntegrated Authority FileLIBRISSystème Universitaire De DocumentationBibliothèque Nationale De FranceBIBSYSUnion List Of Artist NamesMusicBrainzNational Library Of AustraliaNational Diet LibraryNational Library Of The Czech RepublicIstituto Centrale Per Il Catalogo UnicoBiblioteca Nacional De EspañaInstitute For Advanced Technology In The HumanitiesHelp:CategoryCategory:420s BC BirthsCategory:340s BC DeathsCategory:5th-century BC Greek PeopleCategory:4th-century BC Greek PeopleCategory:4th-century BC PhilosophersCategory:4th-century BC PoetsCategory:Academic PhilosophersCategory:Ancient Athenian PhilosophersCategory:Ancient Greek MetaphilosophersCategory:Ancient Greek Political PhilosophersCategory:Ancient Greek MetaphysiciansCategory:Ancient Greek EpistemologistsCategory:Ancient Greek EthicistsCategory:Ancient Greek PhysicistsCategory:Ancient Greek WrestlersCategory:Ancient Greek Slaves And FreedmenCategory:Ancient SyracuseCategory:Attic Greek WritersCategory:Greek Speculative Fiction WritersCategory:Epigrammatists Of The Greek AnthologyCategory:OntologistsCategory:Philosophers Of EducationCategory:Philosophers Of LanguageCategory:Philosophers Of LawCategory:PlatoCategory:PlatonismCategory:Pupils Of SocratesCategory:Moral RealistsCategory:Articles With Encyclopædia Britannica LinksCategory:All Articles That May Contain Original ResearchCategory:Articles That May Contain Original Research From July 2017Category:All Articles With Dead External LinksCategory:Articles With Dead External Links From December 2017Category:Articles With Permanently Dead External LinksCategory:CS1 Maint: BOT: Original-url Status UnknownCategory:Wikipedia Indefinitely Move-protected PagesCategory:Wikipedia Pages Semi-protected Against VandalismCategory:Articles With HCardsCategory:Articles Containing Ancient Greek-language TextCategory:Articles With Specifically Marked Weasel-worded Phrases From July 2017Category:Wikipedia Articles Needing Factual Verification From July 2017Category:Articles Containing Greek-language TextCategory:Pages Using Div Col Without Cols And Colwidth ParametersCategory:Pages Using Columns-list With Deprecated ParametersCategory:Articles Containing Latin-language TextCategory:Wikipedia Articles Incorporating The Template Lives Of The Eminent PhilosophersCategory:Articles With Project Gutenberg LinksCategory:Articles With Internet Archive LinksCategory:Articles With LibriVox LinksCategory:Articles Incorporating A Citation From The 1913 Catholic Encyclopedia With Wikisource ReferenceCategory:AC With 16 ElementsCategory:Wikipedia Articles With VIAF IdentifiersCategory:Wikipedia Articles With LCCN IdentifiersCategory:Wikipedia Articles With ISNI IdentifiersCategory:Wikipedia Articles With GND IdentifiersCategory:Wikipedia Articles With SELIBR IdentifiersCategory:Wikipedia Articles With BNF IdentifiersCategory:Wikipedia Articles With BIBSYS IdentifiersCategory:Wikipedia Articles With ULAN IdentifiersCategory:Wikipedia Articles With MusicBrainz IdentifiersCategory:Wikipedia Articles With NLA IdentifiersCategory:Wikipedia Articles With SBN IdentifiersCategory:Wikipedia Articles With SNAC-ID IdentifiersDiscussion About Edits From This IP Address [n]A List Of Edits Made From This IP Address [y]View The Content Page [c]Discussion About The Content Page [t]This Page Is Protected. You Can View Its Source [e]Visit The Main Page [z]Guides To Browsing WikipediaFeatured Content – The Best Of WikipediaFind Background Information On Current EventsLoad A Random Article [x]Guidance On How To Use And Edit WikipediaFind Out About WikipediaAbout The Project, What You Can Do, Where To Find ThingsA List Of Recent Changes In The Wiki [r]List Of All English Wikipedia Pages Containing Links To This Page [j]Recent Changes In Pages Linked From This Page [k]Upload Files [u]A List Of All Special Pages [q]Wikipedia:AboutWikipedia:General Disclaimer



view link view link view link view link view link